1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446
|
<html>
<head><title>CONSERVATIVITY-OF-DEFCHOOSE.html -- ACL2 Version 3.1</title></head>
<body text=#000000 bgcolor="#FFFFFF">
<h3>CONSERVATIVITY-OF-DEFCHOOSE</h3>proof of conservativity of <code><a href="DEFCHOOSE.html">defchoose</a></code>
<pre>Major Section: <a href="DEFCHOOSE.html">DEFCHOOSE</a>
</pre><p>
This documentation topic provides underlying theory. It is of theoretical
interest only; it has no relationship to the effective use of ACL2.
<p>
The argument below for the conservativity of <a href="DEFCHOOSE.html">defchoose</a> replaces the
terse and somewhat misleading reference to a forcing argument in Appendix B
of the paper by ACL2 authors Kaufmann and Moore, ``Structured Theory
Development for a Mechanized Logic'' (Journal of Automated Reasoning 26,
no. 2 (2001), pp. 161-203).<p>
Our basic idea is to to take a (countable) first-order structure for ACL2, M,
together with a function symbol, f, introduced by <a href="DEFCHOOSE.html">defchoose</a>, and find a
way to expand M with an interpretation of f (without changing the universe of
M) so that e0-induction continues to hold in the expansion. A remark at the
end of this documentation topic shows why care is necessary. A concept
called ``forcing'', originally introduced by Paul Cohen for set theory, has
long since been adapted by logicians (in a simplified form) to model theory.
This simplified model-theoretic forcing provides the means for making our
careful expansion.<p>
The forcing argument presented below is intended to be completely
self-contained for those familiar with basic first-order logic and ACL2. No
background in forcing (model-theoretic or otherwise) is expected, though we
do expect a rudimentary background in first-order logic and familiarity with
the following.<p>
Preliminaries. We write s[p<-p0] to denote the result of extending or
modifying the assignment s by binding p to p0. Now let A be a subset of the
universe U of a first-order structure M. A is said to be ``first-order
definable with parameters'' in M if for some formula phi, variable x, and
assignment s binding the free variables of phi except perhaps for x, A = {a
\in U: M |= phi[s[x<-a]]. Note that we are writing ``\in'' to denote set
membership. Finally, we indicate the end of a proof (or of a theorem
statement, when the proof is omitted) with the symbol ``-|''.<p>
We gratefully acknowledge very helpful feedback from John Cowles, who found
several errors in a draft of this note and suggested the exercises. We also
thank Ruben Gamboa for helpful feedback, and we thank Jim Schmerl for an
observation that led us directly to this proof in the first place.<p>
We are given a consistent first-order theory T, extending the ACL2
ground-zero theory, that satisfies the e0-induction scheme. We wish to show
that the extension of T by the following arbitrary defchoose event is
conservative, where g is a new function symbol.
<pre>
(defchoose g <bound-vars> <free-vars> <body>)
</pre>
Note that by ``the extension of T'' here we mean the extension of T by not
only the new defchoose axiom displayed just below, but also the addition of
e0-induction axioms for formulas in the language with the new defchoose
function symbol, g.
<pre>
<body> -> (LET <free-vars> = g(<bound-vars>) in <body>)
</pre>
By definition of conservativity, since proofs are finite, it clearly suffices
to consider an arbitrary finite subset of T. Then by the completeness,
soundness, and downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorems of first-order logic, it
suffices to show that an arbitrary countable model of T can be expanded
(i.e., by interpreting the new symbol g without changing the universe of the
model) to a model of the corresponding defchoose axiom above, in which all
e0-induction axioms hold in the language of that model.<p>
Below, we will carry out a so-called <em>forcing</em> construction, which
allows us to expand any countable model M of T to a model M[G] that satisfies
e0-induction and also satisfies the above axiom generated from the above
defchoose event. The ideas in this argument are standard in model theory; no
novelty is claimed here.<p>
Fix a countable model M of a theory T that satisfies e0-induction and extends
the ACL2 ground-zero theory. Also fix the above defchoose axiom, where g is
not in the language of T.<p>
We start by defining a partial order P as follows. Let Nb and Nf be the
lengths of <bound-vars> and <free-vars>, respectively. P consists of all fn in
M such that the following formula is true in M. Roughly speaking, it says that
fn is a finite function witnessing the above requirement for g.
<pre>
alistp(fn) &
no-duplicatesp-equal(strip-cars(fn)) &
(forall <bound-vars>, <free-vars> .
(member-equal(cons(<bound-vars>,<free-vars>), fn) ->
(length(<bound-vars>) = Nb &
length(<free-vars>) = Nf &
((exists <free-vars> . <body>) -> <body>))))
</pre>
P is ordered by subset, i.e., we say that p2 <em>extends</em> p1 if p1 is a
subset (not necessarily proper) of p2 (more precisely, M |=
subsetp-equal(p1,p2)).<p>
Remark. The original argument in Appendix B of the aforementioned paper can
essentially be salvaged, as we now show. The key observation is that the
particular choice of P is nearly irrelevant for the argument that follows
below. In particular, we can instead define P to consist of finite one-one
functions with domain contained in the set of natural numbers. More
precisely, consider the following definitions.
<pre>
(defun function-p (fn)
(declare (xargs :guard t))
(and (alistp fn)
(no-duplicatesp-equal (strip-cars fn))))<p>
(defun nat-listp (x)
(declare (xargs :guard t))
(cond ((atom x)
(equal x nil))
(t (and (natp (car x))
(nat-listp (cdr x))))))<p>
(defun nat-function-p (x)
(and (function-p x)
(nat-listp (strip-cars x))))
</pre>
and define inverse as follows.
<pre>
(defun inverse (fn)
(declare (xargs :guard (alistp fn)))
(if (endp fn)
nil
(cons (cons (cdar fn) (caar fn))
(inverse (cdr fn)))))
</pre>
Then P may instead be defined to consist of those fn for which
nat-function-p(fn) & function-p(inverse(fn)). With this alternate definition
of P, the argument below then goes through virtually unchanged, and we get an
expansion M[G] of M in which there is a definable enumeration of the
universe. The conservativity of defchoose then follows easily because the
function being introduced can be defined explicitly using that enumeration
(namely, always pick the least witness in the sense of the enumeration).<p>
End of Remark.<p>
Next we present the relevant forcing concepts from model theory.<p>
A <em>dense</em> subset of P is a subset D of P such that for every p \in P,
there is d \in D such that d extends p. A subset G of P is <em>generic</em>
with respect to a collection Ds of dense subsets of P, also written ``G is
Ds-generic,'' if G is closed under subset (if p2 \in G and p2 extends p1
then p1 \in G), G is pairwise compatible (the union-equal of any two
elements of G is in G), and every set in Ds has non-empty intersection with
G.<p>
For p \in P, we say that a subset D of P is <em>dense beyond</em> p if for all
p1 extending p there exists p2 extending p1 such that p2 \in D. This notion
makes sense even for D not a subset of P if we treat elements of D not in P
as nil.<p>
Proposition 1. For any partial order P and countable collection Ds of dense
subsets of P, there is a Ds-generic subset of P.<p>
Proof. Let Ds = {D0,D1,D2,...}. Define a sequence <p_0,p_1,...> such that
for all i, p_i \in Di and p_(i+1) extends p_i. Let G = {p \in P: for some
i, pi extends p}. Then G is Ds-generic. -|<p>
Note that P is first-order definable (with parameters) in M. Let Df be the
set of dense subsets of P that are first-order definable (with parameters) in
M. A standard argument shows there are only countably many first-order
definitions with parameters in a countable model M -- for example, we can
Goedel number all terms and then all formulas -- hence, Df is countable.<p>
By Proposition 1, let G be Df-generic. Notice that for any list x of length
Nb in M, the set of elements f of P for which x is in the domain of f is
dense and first-order definable. We may thus define a function g0 as
follows: g0(x_1,...,x_Nb) = y if there is some element of G containing the
pair ((x_1 ... x_Nb) . y). It is easy to see that g0 is a total function on
M. Let L be the language of T and let L[g] be the union of L with a set
containing a single new function symbol, g. Let M[G] be the expansion of M
to L[g] obtained by interpreting g to be g0 (see also Proposition 5 below).<p>
So now we have fixed M, P, Df, G, and g0, where G is Df-generic.<p>
Proposition 2. Let Df be the set of dense subsets of P that are first-order
definable (with parameters) in M. Suppose that p \in G and D \in Df. Then for
some q \in G extending p, q \in D.<p>
Proof. Let D0 be the set of p' \in D that either extend p or have no
extension in D that extends p. We leave it as a straightforward exercise to
show that D0 is dense, and D0 is clearly first-order definable (with
parameters) in M. So by genericity of G, we may pick q \in D0 such that q
\in G. Thus q \in D. By definition of generic, some extension q1 of both
p and q belongs to G. Pick q2 \in D extending q1; thus q has an extension
in D that extends p (namely, q2), so by definition of D0, q extends p. -|<p>
Definition of forcing. Let phi(x1,...,xk) be a first-order formula in L[g]
and let p \in P. We define a formula of L, denoted ``p ||- phi'' (``p
forces phi''), by recursion on phi (in the metatheory) as follows. (Here, we
view ``or'' and ``forall'' as abbreviations.)<p>
<blockquote>
If phi is atomic, then let phi'(A) be the result of replacing, inside-out,
each subterm of the form g(x_1,...,x_Nb) with the term (cdr (assoc-equal
(list x_1 ... x_Nb) A)), where A is neither p nor a variable occurring in
phi. Then p ||- phi is defined as follows: ``The set {A \in P: A extends
p and phi'(A)} is dense beyond p''. That is, p ||- phi is the following
formula:
<pre>
(forall p1 \in P extending p)
(exists p2 \in P extending p1) phi'(p2).
</pre>
p ||- ~phi is: (forall p' \in P extending p) ~(p' ||- phi)<p>
p ||- phi_1 & phi_2 is: (p ||- phi_1) & (p ||- phi_2)<p>
p ||- (exists x) phi is: (exists x) (p ||- phi)
</blockquote>
<p>
We will need the following definition later.<p>
Definition. p ||-w phi (p <em>weakly forces</em> phi) is an abbreviation for p
||- ~~phi.<p>
The following exercises were suggested by John Cowles as a means for gaining
familiarity with the definition of forcing.<p>
Exercise 1. Consider the formula (phi_1 OR phi_2) as an abbreviation for
~(~phi_1 & ~phi_2), Show that p ||- (phi_1 OR phi_2) is equivalent to the
following.
<pre>
(forall p' \in P extending p) (exists p'' \in P extending p')
((p'' ||- phi_1) OR (p'' ||- phi_2))
</pre>
<p>
Exercise 2. Consider the formula (forall x)phi as an abbreviation for
~(exists x)~phi, Show that p ||- (forall x)phi is equivalent to the following.
<pre>
(forall x)
(forall p1 \in P extending p)
(exists p2 \in P extending p1) (p2 ||- phi).
</pre>
Exercise 3. Prove that p ||-w phi is equivalent to the following.
<pre>
(forall p' \in P extending p)
(exists p'' \in P extending p') (p'' ||- phi).
</pre>
<p>
Exercise 4. Let phi be a formula of L[g]. Prove:
M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p0]] implies
M |= (p ||-w phi)[s[p<-p0]].<p>
Exercise 5. Let phi be a formula of L[g]. Prove:
M |= (p ||- ~phi)[s[p<-p0]] iff
M |= (p ||-w ~phi)[s[p<-p0]].<p>
[End of exercises.]<p>
The definition of forcing stipulates how to view ``p ||- phi(x1,...,xk)'' as
a new formula theta(p,x1,...,xk). That is, ``||-'' transforms formulas, so
for any first-order formula phi, ``p ||- phi'' is just another first-order
formula. That observation shows that a formula such as ((p ||- phi) OR (p
||- ~phi)) is really just another first-order formula. The following
proposition thus follows easily.<p>
Proposition 3. For any formula phi of L[g], {p0: M |= ((p ||- phi) OR (p ||-
~phi))[s[p<-p0]]]} is a dense subset of P, which (since it is first-order
definable with parameters in M) intersects G. -|<p>
The following proposition is easily proved by a structural induction on phi,
and is left to the reader.<p>
Proposition 4. Let phi be a formula of L[g]. Suppose <code>p0 in P</code>,
<code>p1 in P</code>,<br>
M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p0]] and p1 extends p0. Then<br>
M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p1]]. -|<p>
We will also need the following.<p>
Proposition 5. The following is dense for any finite set S of Nb-tuples: {p
\in P: for some <x_1 ... x_Nb> \in S, (list x_1 ... x_Nb) \in
strip-cars(p)}. Thus, the function g0 is a total function. -|<p>
The next lemma tells us that the sentences true in M[G] are those that are
forced by an element of G.<p>
Truth Lemma. Let phi be a formula in L[g], let s be an assignment to the
free variables of phi, and let p be a variable not in the domain of s. Then
M[G] |= phi[s] iff for some p0 \in G, M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p0]].<p>
Proof. The proof is by induction on the structure of phi. First suppose phi
is atomic. Let D* be the set of elements p0 \in P such that every
assoc-equal evaluation from the definition of forcing phi returns a pair when
A is bound to p0. (Intuitively, this means that p0 is a sufficiently large
approximation from any G containing p0 to make sense of phi in M[G].) We
make the following claim.
<pre>
(*) For all p0 \in G such that p0 \in D*,
M[G] |= phi[s] iff M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p0]].
</pre>
<p>
To prove the claim, fix p0 in both G and D*, and recall the function g0
constructed from G in the definition of M[G]. Suppose that t_1, ..., t_Nb
are terms and g(t_1, ..., t_Nb) is a subterm of phi. Then s assigns a value
in M to each of the t_i. Let a_i be the value assigned by s to t_i. Then
g0(a_1, ..., a_Nb) = (cdr (assoc-equal (list a_1 ... a_Nb) p0)), as the
assoc-equal is a pair (since p0 \in D*) and has the indicated value (because
p0 \in G). It follows by the definition of formula phi' in the definition
of forcing:
<pre>
M[G] |= phi[s] iff M |= phi'(p)[s[p<-p0]]
</pre>
Moreover, because p0 \in D* it is clear that this holds if p0 is replaced by
an arbitrary extension of p0. Then (*) easily follows.<p>
By Proposition 5, D* is dense, so there is some p0 in the intersection of D*
and G. The forward direction of the conclusion then follows by (*). The
reverse direction is clear from (*) by application of Proposition 2 to D* and
Proposition 4.<p>
Next, suppose M[G] |= ~phi[x]. Then it is not the case that M[G] |= phi, so
by the inductive hypothesis, there is no p0 \in G for which M |= (p ||-
phi)[s[p<-p0]]. By Proposition 3, there is p0 \in G for which M |= (p ||-
~phi)[s[p<-p0]]. For the other direction, suppose it is not the case that
M[G] |= ~phi[s]. So M[G] |= phi[s], and by the inductive hypothesis, there
is p0 \in G for which M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p0]]. It follows that there is
no p1 \in G for which M |= (p ||- ~phi)[s[p<-p1]], since from such p1 we can
find a common extension p2 of p0 and p1 (since G is generic), and since p2
extends p0 then by Proposition 4, M |= (p ||- phi)[s[p<-p2]], contradicting
(by definition of forcing) M |= (p ||- ~phi)[s[p<-p1]] since p2 extends p1.<p>
The case (phi_1 & phi_2) follows easily from the inductive hypothesis. For
the forward direction, apply Proposition 4 and the observation that by
genericity, if p0 \in G and p1 \in G then p0 and p1 they have a common
extension in G.<p>
Finally, the case (exists x) phi follows trivially from the inductive
hypothesis. -|<p>
Truth Lemma Corollary. The Truth Lemma holds with ||-w replacing ||-.<p>
Proof. This is clear by applying the Truth Lemma to ~~phi. -|<p>
Here is our main theorem. Recall that all first-order theories in our ACL2
context satisfy the e0-induction scheme.<p>
Theorem. M[G] satisfies e0-induction.<p>
Proof. We consider an arbitrary instance of e0-induction in L[g], stated
using a strict well-founded relation <| and a formula phi. We write phi(y)
to indicate that y may be among the free variables of phi, and phi(y<-x) to
denote the result of substituting x for y in phi.
<pre>
theta(y): (forall y) [((forall x <| y) phi(y<-x)) -> phi(y)]
-> (forall y) phi(y)
</pre>
Our goal is to prove that theta holds in M[G].<p>
Below, we abuse notation by leaving assignments implicit and by writing ``p
||- phi(y0)'' to signify that the formula (p ||- phi(y)) is true in M under
the extension of the explicit assignment that binds y to y0. We believe that
the intended meaning will be clear.<p>
Consider the following set D.
<pre>
D = {p \in P: either p ||-w phi(y0) for all y0,
or else
for some y0, p ||- ~phi(y0) and
for all y1 <| y0 p ||-w phi(y1)}.
</pre>
The set D is clearly first-order definable (with parameters) in M. We claim
that D is a dense subset of P. For suppose p0 \in P; we find p1 \in D
extending p0, as follows. If p0 ||-w phi(y0) for all y0, then we may take p1
to be p0. Otherwise, by definition of ||-w and ||-, there is some y0 such
that for some extension p0' of p0, p0' ||- ~phi(y0). Pick a <|-minimal such
y0, and correspondingly pick p1 so that p1 extends p0 and p1 ||- ~phi(y0).
In order to show that p1 \in D, it remains to show that for all y1 <| y0,
p1 ||-w phi(y1), i.e., there is no q extending p1 such that q ||- ~phi(y1).
This is indeed the case since otherwise q and y1 would contradict the
<|-minimality of y0.<p>
Applying the genericity of G and just-proved density of D, pick p0 \in G
such that p0 \in D. If p0 ||-w phi(y0) for all y0, then by the Truth Lemma
Corollary, M[G] |= phi(y0) for all y0, and thus M[G] |= theta. Otherwise,
since p0 \in D we may choose y0 such that p0 ||- ~phi(y0) and for all y1 <|
y0, p0 ||-w phi(y1). By the Truth Lemma and its corollary, since p0 \in G
we have:
<pre>
(1) M[G] |= ~phi(y0).
(2) For all y1 <| y0, M[G] |= phi(y1).
</pre>
It follows that the antecedent of theta is false in M[G], as witnessed by y =
y0; thus M[G] |= theta. -|<p>
Remark. We close by returning, as promised above, to the question of why so
much care is necessary in constructing an expansion of M. We assume
familiarity here with the notion of a ``non-standard'' natural number of M,
i.e., one that is greater than the interpretation of any term that has the
form (+ 1 1 1 ... 1). Here is a very simple example that illustrates the
need for some care. Consider the following event, which introduces a
function foo with the following property: for all x, if natp(x) then
natp(foo(x)).
<pre>
(defchoose foo (y) (x)
(implies (natp x) (natp y)))
</pre>
Certainly we can build a model of the above property from a model M of the
ground-zero theory, by interpreting foo so that for all x for which M
satisfies natp(x), foo(x) is also a natp in M. But suppose we start with a
non-standard model M of the ground-zero theory, and we happen to define
foo(x) to be 1 for all non-standard natural numbers x and 0 for all other x.
The resulting expansion of M will not satisfy the e0-induction scheme or even
the ordinary natural number induction scheme: foo(0)=0 holds in that
expansion as does the implication foo(n)=0 => foo(n+1)=0 for every natural
number n of M, standard or not; and yet foo(k)=0 fails for every non-standard
natural number k of M.
<br><br><br><a href="acl2-doc.html"><img src="llogo.gif"></a> <a href="acl2-doc-index.html"><img src="index.gif"></a>
</body>
</html>
|