File: secE3.html

package info (click to toggle)
anarchism 15.3-3
  • links: PTS, VCS
  • area: main
  • in suites: bookworm, bullseye, sid, trixie
  • size: 26,216 kB
  • sloc: makefile: 10
file content (128 lines) | stat: -rw-r--r-- 95,135 bytes parent folder | download | duplicates (2)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
<!DOCTYPE html>
<html>
  <head>
  <meta http-equiv="Content-Type" content="text/html; charset=utf-8" />
  <title>E.3 Can private property rights protect the environment? | Anarchist Writers</title>
  </head>
  <body>
  <div class="content clear-block">
    <h1>E.3 Can private property rights protect the environment?</h1>
<p>Environmental issues have become increasingly important over the decades. When Murray Bookchin wrote his first works on our  ecological problems in the 1950s, he was only one of a small band. Today, even right-wing politicians have to give at least some lip-service to environmental concerns while corporations are keen to present their green credentials to the general  public (even if they do not, in fact, have any).</p>
<p>As such, there has been a significant change. This is better late  than never, considering that the warnings made by the likes of  Bookchin in the 1950s and 1960s have come true to a threateningly  worrying degree. Sadly, eco-anarchist solutions are still ignored  but that is unsurprising as they go to the heart of the ecological  problem, namely domination within humanity as the precondition for  the domination of nature and the workings of the capitalist economy. It is hardly likely that those who practice and benefit from that oppression and exploitation will admit that they are causing the  problems! Hence the need to appear green in order to keep a  fundamentally anti-green system going.</p>
<p>Of course, some right-wingers are totally opposed to ecological  issues. They seriously seem to forget without a viable ecology,  there would be no capitalism. Ayn Rand, for example, dismissed  environmental concerns as being anti-human and had little problem  with factory chimneys belching smoke into the atmosphere (her  fondness for chimneys and skyscrapers would have have made  Freud reach for his notepad). As Bob Black once noted, <i>"Rand  remarked that she <b>worshipped</b> smokestacks. For her . . .  they not only stood for, they <b>were</b> the epitome of human  accomplishment. She must have meant it since she was something of  a human smokestack herself; she was a chain smoker, as were the  other rationals in her entourage. In the end she abolished her  own breathing: she died of lung cancer."</i> [<i>"Smokestack Lightning,"</i>  <b>Friendly Fire</b>, p. 62] The fate of this guru of capitalism is a  forewarning for our collective one if we ignore the environment  and our impact on it.</p>
<p>The key to understanding why so many on the right are dismissive of ecological concerns is simply that ecology cannot be squeezed into their narrow individualistic property based politics. Ecology is about interconnectiveness, about change and interaction, about the sources of life and how we interact with them and they with us.  Moreover, ecology is rooted in the <b>quality</b> of life and goes not automatically view quantity as the key factor. As such, the notion that more is better does not strike the ecologist as, in itself, a good thing. The idea that growth is good as such is the principle associated with cancer. Ecology also destroys the individualistic  premise of capitalist economics. It exposes the myth that the market ensures everyone gets exactly what they want -- for if you consume  eco-friendly products but others do not then you are affected by their  decisions as the environmental impact affects all. Equally, the notion  that the solution to GM crops should letting "the market" decide fails  to take into account that such crops spread into local eco-systems and  contaminate whole areas (not to mention the issue of corporate power enclosing another part of the commons). The market "solution" in this  case would result in everyone, to some degree, consuming GM crops  eventually. None of this can be fitted into the capitalist ideology.</p>
<p>However, while vocal irrational anti-green perspectives lingers on in  some sections of the right (particularly those funded by the heaviest  polluters), other supporters of capitalism have considered the problems  of ecological destruction in some degree. Some of this is, of course, simply greenwashing (i.e., using PR and advertising to present a green  image while conducting business as usual). Some of it is funding  think tanks which use green-sounding names, imagery and rhetoric to help pursue a decidedly anti-ecological practice and agenda. Some of is, to some degree, genuine. Al Gore's campaign to make the world  aware of the dangers of climate change is obviously sincere and  important work (although it is fair to point out the lack of green policies being raised during his 2000 Presidential election campaign and the poverty of his proposed solutions and means of change). Nicholas Stern's 2006 report on climate change produced for the UK  government is another example and it gives an insight into the   mentality of such environmentalists. The report did produce quite an  impact (plus its dismissal by the usual suspects). The key reason for  that was, undoubtedly, due to it placing a money sum on the dangers of  environmental disruption. Such is capitalism -- people and planet can  go to the dogs, but any threat to profits must be acted upon. As the  British PM at the time put it, any Climate Change Bill must be <i>"fully  compatible with the interests of businesses and consumers as well."</i>  Which is ironic, as it is the power of money which is causing the bulk  of the problems we face.</p>
<p>Which is what we will discuss here, namely whether private property can be used to solve our environmental problems. Liberal environmentalists base  their case on capitalist markets aided with some form of state intervention.  Neo-liberal and right-"libertarian" environmentalists base their case purely  on capitalist markets and reject any role for the state bar that of defining  and enforcing private property rights. Both, however, assume that capitalism will remain and tailor their policies around it. Anarchists question that particularly assumption particularly given, as we discussed in  <a href="secE1.html">section E.1</a>,  the fundamental reason why capitalism cannot be green is its irrational  "grow-or-die" dynamic. However, there are other aspects of the system which  contribute to capitalism bringing ecological crisis sooner rather than later.  These flow from the nature of private property and the market competition it  produces (this discussion, we should stress, ignores such factors as  economic power which will be addressed in <a href="secE3.html#sece32">section E.3.2</a>).</p>
<p>The market itself causes ecological problems for two related reasons:  externalities and the price mechanism. It is difficult making informed  consumption decisions under capitalism because rather than provide  enough information to make informed decisions, the market hinders the  flow of relevant information and suppresses essential knowledge. This is  particularly the case with environmental information and knowledge. Simply put,  we have no way of knowing from a given price the ecological impact of the  products we buy. One such area of suppressed information is that involving externalities. This is a commonly understood problem. The market actively rewards  those companies which inflict externalities on society. This is the <i>"routine and  regular harms caused to <b>others</b> -- workers, consumers, communities, the  environment."</i> These are termed <i>"externalities"</i> in <i>"the coolly technical jargon  of economics"</i> and the capitalist company is an <i>"externalising  machine"</i> and it is <i>"no exaggeration to say that the corporation's built in  compulsion to externalise its costs is at the root of many of the world's  social and environmental ills."</i> [Joel Bakan, <b>The Corporation</b>, p. 60 and  p. 61]</p>
<p>The logic is simple, by externalising (imposing) costs on others (be it  workers, customers or the planet) a firm can reduce its costs and make  higher profits. Thus firms have a vested interest in producing externalities.  To put it crudely, pollution pays while ecology costs. Every pound a  business spends on environmental protections is one less in profits.  As such, it makes economic sense to treat the environment like a dump  and externalise costs by pumping raw industrial effluent into the  atmosphere, rivers, and oceans. The social cost of so doing weighs little  against the personal profits that result from inflicting diffuse losses onto  the general public. Nor should we discount the pressure of market forces in this process. In order to survive on the market, firms may have to act in ways  which, while profitable in the short-run, are harmful in the long term. For  example, a family-owned farm may be forced to increase production using  environmentally unsound means simply in order to avoid bankruptcy.</p>
<p>As well as economic incentives, the creation of externalities flows from the  price mechanism itself. The first key issue, as green economist E. F. Schumacher stressed, is that the market is based on <i>"total quantification at the expense of  qualitative differences; for private enterprise is not concerned with what it  produces but only what it gains from production."</i> This means that the <i>"judgement  of economics . . . is an extremely <b>fragmentary</b> judgement; out of the large  number of aspects which in real life have to be seen and judged together before  a decision can be taken, economics supplies only one -- whether a thing yields  a profit <b>to those who undertake it</b> or not."</i> [<b>Small is Beautiful</b>, p. 215 and p. 28] This leads to a simplistic decision making perspective:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "Everything becomes crystal clear after you have reduced reality to one --  one only -- of its thousand aspects. You know what to do -- whatever produces  profits; you know what to avoid -- whatever reduces them or makes a loss. And  there is at the same time a perfect measuring rod for the degree of success or  failure. Let no-one befog the issue by asking whether a particular action is conducive to the wealth and well-being of society, whether it leads to  moral, aesthetic, or cultural enrichment. Simply find out whether it pays."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 215]
</p></blockquote>
<p>This means that key factors in decision making are, at best, undermined by  the pressing need to make profits or, at worse, simply ignored as a handicap. So <i>"in the market place, for practical reasons, innumerable qualitative  distinctions which are of vital importance for man and society are  suppressed; they are not allowed to surface. Thus the reign of quantity  celebrates its greatest triumphs in 'The Market.'"</i> This feeds the drive to externalise costs, as it is <i>"based on a definition of cost which excludes  all 'free goods,' that is to say, the entire God-given environment, except  for those parts of it that have been privately appropriated. This means  that an activity can be economic although it plays hell with the environment, and that a competing activity, if at some cost it protects and conserves the  environment, will be uneconomic."</i> To summarise: <i>"it is inherent in the  methodology of economics to <b>ignore man's dependence on the natural world.</b>"</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 30 and p. 29]</p>
<p>Ultimately, should our decision-making be limited to a single criteria,  namely whether it makes someone a profit? Should our environment be handed  over to a system which bases itself on confusing efficient resource allocation  with maximising profits in an economy marked by inequalities of wealth and,  consequently, on unequal willingness and ability to pay? In other words,  biodiversity, eco-system stability, clean water and air, and so forth only  become legitimate social goals when the market places a price on them  sufficient for a capitalist to make money from them. Such a system can only fail to achieve a green society simply because ecological concerns cannot be reduced to one criteria (<i>"The discipline of economics achieves its  formidable resolving power by transforming what might otherwise be  considered qualitative matters into quantitative issues with a single  metric and, as it were, a bottom line: profit or loss."</i> [James C. Scott,  <b>Seeing like a State</b>, p. 346]). This is particularly the case when even economists admit that the market under-supplies public goods, of which a clean and aesthetically pleasing environment is the classic example. Markets may reflect, to some degree, individual consumer preferences distorted by income distribution but they are simply incapable of  reflecting collective values (a clean environment and spectacular views  are inherently collective goods and cannot be enclosed). As a result,  capitalists will be unlikely to invest in such projects as they cannot  make everyone who uses them pay for the privilege.</p>
<p>Then there is the tendency for the market to undermine and destroy  practical and local knowledge on which truly ecological decisions need to be based. Indigenous groups, for example, have accumulated an enormous body of knowledge about local ecological conditions and species which are ignored in economic terms or eliminated by  competition with those with economic power. Under markets, in other words, unarticulated knowledge of soil conditions and bio-diversity which have considerable value for long-term sustainability is usually lost when it meets agribusiness.</p>
<p>Practical knowledge, i.e. local and tacit knowledge which James C. Scott  terms metis, is being destroyed and replaced <i>"by standardised formulas  legible from the centre"</i> and this <i>"is virtually inscribed in the activities  of both the state and large-scale bureaucratic capitalism."</i> The <i>"logic  animating the project . . . is one of control and appropriation. Local  knowledge, because it is dispersed and relatively autonomous, is all  but unappropriable. The reduction or, more utopian still, the elimination  of metis and the local control its entails are preconditions, in the case  of the state, of administrative order and fiscal appropriation and, in  the case of the large capitalism firm, of worker discipline and profit."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 335-6] Green socialist John O'Neill provides a similar  analysis:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "far from fostering the existence of practical and local knowledge, the spread of markets often appears to do the opposite: the growth of global markets is associated with the disappearance of knowledge that is local and practical, and the growth of abstract codifiable information . . . the market as a mode of co-ordination appears to foster forms of abstract codifiable knowledge . . . The knowledge of weak and marginal actors in markets, such as peasant and  marginalised indigenous communities, tends to be lost to those who hold market power. The epistemic value of knowledge claims bear no direct relation to their market value. Local and often unarticulated knowledge of soil conditions and crop varieties that have considerable value for long-term sustainability of  agriculture has no value in markets and hence is always liable  to loss when it comes into contact with oil-based agricultural  technologies of those who do have market power. The undermining  of local practical knowledge in market economies has also been  exacerbated by the global nature of both markets and large corporate actors who require knowledge that is transferable across different cultures and contexts and hence abstract and codifiable . . . Finally, the demand for commensurability and calculability runs against the defence of local and practical knowledge. This is not just a theoretical problem but one with real institutional embodiments. The market encourages a spirit of calculability . . . That spirit is the starting point for the algorithmic account of practical reason which requires explicit common measures for rational choice and fails to acknowledge the existence of choice founded upon practical judgement. More generally it is not amicable to forms of knowledge that are practical, local and uncodifiable."</i>  [<b>Markets, Deliberation and Environment</b>, pp. 192-3]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Thus the market tends to replace traditional forms of agriculture and working practices (and the complex knowledge and expertises  associated with both) with standardised techniques which aim to extract as much profit in the short-term as possible by concentrating power into the hands of management and their appointed experts. That they cannot even begin to comprehend the local conditions and practical knowledge and skills required to effectively use the resources available in a sustainable manner should go without saying. Unfortunately, the economic clout of big business is such that it can defeat traditional forms of knowledge in the short-term (the long-term effect of such  exploitation is usually considered someone else's problem).</p>
<p>So, given this analysis, it comes as no surprise to anarchists that private property has not protected the environment. In fact, it is one of the root causes of our ecological problems. Markets hide the  ecological and health information necessary for environmentally  sound decisions. Ultimately, environmental issues almost always  involve value judgements and the market stops the possibility of  producing a public dialogue in which these values can be discussed  and enriched. Instead, it replaces this process by an aggregation  of existing preferences (shaped by economic pressures and necessity)  skewed in favour of this generation's property owners. An individual's  interest, like that of the public as a whole, is not something which  exists independently of the decision-making processes used but rather  is something which is shaped by them. Atomistic processes focused on  a simplistic criteria will produce simplistic decisions which have  collectively irrational results. Collective decision making based on  equal participation of all will produce decisions which reflect <b>all</b>  the concerns of <b>all</b> affected in a process which will help produce  empowered and educated individuals along with informed decisions.</p>
<p>Some disagree. For these the reason why there is environmental damage is not due to too much private property but because there is too little.  This perspective derives from neo-classical and related economic theory and it argues that ecological harm occurs because environmental goods and bads  are unpriced. They come free, in other words. This suggests that the best way to protect the environment is to privatise everything and to create markets in all areas of life. This perspective, needless to say, is entirely  the opposite of the standard eco-anarchist one which argues that our  environmental problems have their root in market mechanisms, private  property and the behaviour they generate. As such, applying market norms  even more rigorously and into areas of life that were previously protected from markets will tend to make ecological problems worse, not better.</p>
<p>As would be expected, the pro-property perspective is part of the wider turn to free(r) market capitalism since the 1970s. With the apparent  success of Thatcherism and Reaganism (at least for the people who count  under capitalism, i.e. the wealthy) and the fall of Stalinism in the  Eastern Block, the 1980s and 1990s saw a period of capitalist triumphantism.  This lead to an increase in market based solutions to every conceivable social problem, regardless of how inappropriate and/or insane the  suggestions were. This applies to ecological issues as well. The  publication of <b>Free Market Environmentalism</b> by Terry L. Anderson  and Donald R. Leal in 1991 saw ideas previously associated with the right-"libertarian" fringe become more mainstream and, significantly, supported by corporate interests and the think-tanks and politicians they fund.</p>
<p>Some see it as a deliberate plan to counteract a growing ecological  movement which aims to change social, political and economic structures  in order to get at the root cases of our environmental problems. Activist  Sara Diamond suggested that <i>"[s]ome farsighted corporations are finding  that the best 'bulwark' against 'anti-corporation' environmentalism is  the creation and promotion of an alternative model called 'free market  environmentalism.'"</i> [<i>"Free Market Environmentalism,"</i> <b>Z Magazine</b>,  December 1991] Whatever the case, the net effect of this reliance on markets  is to depoliticise environmental debates, to transform issues which involve  values and affect many people into ones in which the property owner is  given priority and where the criteria for decision making becomes one  of profit and loss. It means, effectively, ending debates over <b>why</b>  ecological destruction happens and what we should do about it and  accepting the assumptions, institutions and social relationships of  capitalism as a given as well as privatising yet more of the world and  handing it over to capitalists. Little wonder it is being proposed  as an alternative by corporations concerned about their green image.  At the very least, it is fair to say that the corporations who punt  free market environmentalism as an alternative paradigm for environmental policy making are not expecting to pay more by internalising their costs by so doing.</p>
<p>As with market fundamentalism in general, private property based  environmentalism appears to offer solutions simply because it fails to take into account the reality of any actual capitalist system. The  notion that all we have to do is let markets work ignores the fact  that any theoretical claim for the welfare superiority of free-market  outcomes falls when we look at any real capitalist market. Once we  introduce, say, economic power, imperfect competition, public goods,  externalities or asymmetric information then the market quickly  becomes a god with feet of clay. This is what we will explore in  the rest of this section while the <a href="secE4.html">next section</a> will discuss a  specific example of how laissez-faire capitalism cannot be ecological as proved by one of its most fervent ideologues. Overall, anarchists  feel we have a good case on why is unlikely that private property  can protect the environment.</p>
<h2><a name="sece31">E.3.1 Will privatising nature save it?</a></h2>
<p>No, it will not. To see why, it is only necessary to look at the arguments and assumptions of those who advocate such solutions to our ecological problems.</p>
<p>The logic behind the notion of privatising the planet is simple.  Many of our environmental problems stem, as noted in the  <a href="secE3.html">last section</a>, from externalities.  According to the "market advocates" this is due to there being unowned resources for if someone owned them, they would sue whoever or whatever was polluting them. By means of private property and  the courts, pollution would end. Similarly, if an endangered species or eco-system were privatised then the new owners would  have an interest in protecting them if tourists, say, were willing to pay to see them. Thus the solution to environmental problems  is simple. Privatise everything and allow people's natural incentive  to care for their own property take over.</p>
<p>Even on this basic level, there are obvious problems. Why assume that  <b>capitalist</b> property rights are the only ones, for example? However, the crux of the problem is clear enough. This solution only works if we assume that the "resources" in question make their owners a profit or if they are willing and able to track down the polluters. Neither assumption is robust enough to carry the weight that capitalism places on our planet's environment. There is no automatic mechanism by which  capitalism will ensure that environmentally sound practices will  predominate. In fact, the opposite is far more likely.</p>
<p>At its most basic, the underlying rationale is flawed. It argues that it is only by giving the environment a price can we compare its use for  different purposes. This allows the benefits from preserving a forest  to be compared to the benefits of cutting it down and building a shopping  centre over it. Yet by "benefits" it simply means economic benefits, i.e.  whether it is profitable for property owners to do so, rather than  ecologically sensible. This is an important difference. If more money  can be made in turning a lake into a toxic waste dump then, logically,  its owners will do so. Similarly, if timber prices are not rising at  the prevailing profit or interest rate, then a self-interested firm will  seek to increase its profits and cut-down its trees as fast as possible, investing the returns elsewhere. They may even sell such cleared land  to other companies to develop. This undermines any claim that private  property rights and environmental protection go hand-in-hand.</p>
<p>As Glenn Albrecht argues, such a capitalist "solution" to environmental  problems is only <i>"likely to be effective in protecting species [or  ecosystems] which are commercially important only if the commercial  value of that species [or ecosystem] exceeds that of other potential  sources of income that could be generated from the same 'natural  capital' that the species inhabits If, for example, the conservation of species for ecotourism generates income which is greater than that which could be gained by using their habit for the growing of cash crops, then the private property rights of the owners of the habitat will effectively protect those species . . . However, this model becomes progressively less  plausible when we are confronted with rare but commercially unimportant  species [or ecosystems] versus very large development proposals that are  inconsistent with their continual existence. The less charismatic the  species, the more 'unattractive' the ecosystem, the more likely it will  be that the development proposal will proceed. The 'rights' of developers will eventually win out over species and ecosystems since . . . bio-diversity itself has no right to exist and even if it did, the clash of rights between an endangered species and multi-national capital would be a very uneven contest."</i> [<i>"Ethics, Anarchy and Sustainable Development"</i>,  pp. 95-118, <b>Anarchist Studies</b>, vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 104-5]</p>
<p>So the conservation of endangered species or eco-systems is not automatically achieved using the market. This is especially the case  when there is little, or no, economic value in the species or eco-system  in question. The most obvious example is when there is only a limited  profit to be made from a piece of land by maintaining it as the habitat  of a rare species. If any alternative economic uses for that land yields  a greater profit then that land will be developed. Moreover, if a species looses its economic value as a commodity then the property owners will become indifferent to its survival. Prices change and  so an investment which made sense today may not look so good tomorrow.  So if the market price of a resource decreases then it becomes unlikely  that its ecological benefits will outweigh its economic ones. Overall,  regardless of the wider ecological importance of a specific eco-system  or species it is likely that their owner will prioritise short-term  profits over environmental concerns. It should go without saying that  threatened or endangered eco-systems and species will be lost under a  privatised regime as it relies on the willingness of profit-orientated  companies and individuals to take a loss in order to protect the  environment.</p>
<p>Overall, advocates of market based environmentalism need to present a case that <b>all</b> plants, animals and eco-systems are valuable  commodities in the same way as, say, fish are. While a case for market-based environmentalism can be made by arguing that fish  have a market price and, as such, owners of lakes, rivers and oceans would have an incentive to keep their waters clean in order to sell fish on the market, the same cannot be said of all species and habitats. Simply put, not all creatures, plants and eco-systems  with an ecological value will have an economic one as well.</p>
<p>Moreover, markets can send mixed messages about the environmental  policies which should be pursued. This may lead to over investment  in some areas and then a slump. For example, rising demand for recycled  goods may inspire an investment boom which, in turn, may lead to  over-supply and then a crash, with plants closing as the price falls  due to increased supply. Recycling may then become economically  unviable, even though it remains ecologically essential. In addition,  market prices hardly provide an accurate signal regarding the "correct"  level of ecological demands in a society as they are constrained by  income levels and reflect the economic pressures people are under.  Financial security and income level play a key role, for in the market  not all votes are equal. A market based allocation of environmental  goods and bads does not reflect the obvious fact the poor may appear  to value environmental issues less than the wealthy in this scheme  simply because their preferences (as expressed in the market) are  limited by lower budgets.</p>
<p>Ultimately, market demand can change without the underlying demand for a specific good changing. For example, since the 1970s the  real wages of most Americans have stagnated while inequality  has soared. As a result, fewer households can afford to go  on holidays to wilderness areas or buy more expensive  ecologically friendly products. Does that imply that the people  involved now value the environment less simply because they now  find it harder to make ends meet? Equally, if falling living  standards force people to take jobs with dangerous environmental  consequences does than really provide an accurate picture of people's  desires? It takes a giant leap of faith (in the market) to assume that  falling demand for a specific environmental good implies that reducing environmental damage has become less valuable to people. Economic  necessity may compel people to act against their best impulses, even  strongly felt natural values (an obvious example is that during  recessions people may be more willing to tolerate greenhouse gas  emissions simply because they need the work).</p>
<p>Nor can it be claimed that all the relevant factors in ecological  decision making can take the commodity form, i.e. be given a price. This means that market prices do not, in fact, actually reflect  people's environmental values. Many aspects of our environment  simply cannot be given a market price (how can you charge people  to look at beautiful scenery?). Then there is the issue of how to  charge a price which reflects the demand of people who wish to know  that, say, the rainforest or wilderness exists and is protected  but who will never visit either? Nor are future generations taken  into account by a value that reflects current willingness to pay  and might not be consistent with long-term welfare or even survival.  And how do you factor in the impact a cleaner environment has on  protecting or extending human lives? Surely a healthy environment  is worth much more than simply lost earnings and the medical bills   and clean-up activities saved? At best, you could factor this in  by assuming that the wage premium of workers in dangerous  occupations reflects it but a human life is, surely, worth  more than the wages required to attract workers into dangerous  working conditions. Wages are <b>not</b> an objective measure  of the level of environmental risks workers are willing to tolerate  as they are influenced by the overall state of the economy, the  balance of class power and a whole host of other factors. Simply  put, fear of unemployment and economic security will ensure that workers tolerate jobs that expose them and their communities to  high levels of environmental dangers.</p>
<p>Economic necessity drives decisions in the so-called "free" market  (given a choice between clean air and water and having a job, many  people would choose the latter simply because they have to in order  to survive). These factors can only be ignored which means that  environmental values <b>cannot</b>  be treated like commodities and market  prices <b>cannot</b> accurately reflect environmental values. The key thing  to remember is that the market does not meet demand, it meets <b>effective</b>  demand (i.e. demands backed up with money). Yet people want endangered  species and eco-systems protected even if there is no effective demand  for them on the market (nor could be). We will return to this critical  subject in the <a href="secE3.html#sece32">next section</a>.</p>
<p>Then there are the practicalities of privatising nature. How, for  example, do we "privatise" the oceans? How do we "privatise" whales  and sharks in order to conserve them? How do we know if a whaling ship kills "your" whale? And what if "your" shark feeds on "my" fish? From whom do we buy these resources in the first place? What courts  must be set up to assess and try crimes and define damages? Then  there are the costs of defining and enforcing private rights by  means of the courts. This would mean individual case-by-case adjudications which increase transaction costs. Needless to say, such cases will be influenced by the resources available to both sides. Moreover, the judiciary is almost always the least accountable and representative branch of the state and so turning environmental policy decisions over to them will hardly ensure that public concerns are at the foremost of any decision (such a move would also help  undermine trial by jury as juries often tend to reward sizeable  damages against corporations in such cases, a factor corporations are all too aware of).</p>
<p>This brings us to the problem of actually proving that the particles of  a specific firm has inflicted a specific harm on a particular person and their property. Usually, there are multiple firms engaging in polluting the atmosphere and it would be difficult, if not impossible, to legally establish the liability of any particular firm. How to identify which  particular polluter caused the smog which damaged your lungs and garden?  Is it an individual company? A set of companies? All companies? Or is  it transportation? In which case, is it the specific car which finally  caused your cancer or a specific set of car uses? Or all car users? Or  is it the manufacturers for producing such dangerous products in the  first place?</p>
<p>Needless to say, even this possibility is limited to the current  generation. Pollution afflicts future generations as well and  it is impossible for their interests to be reflected in court for  "future harm" is not the question, only present harm counts. Nor can non-human species or eco-systems sue for damage, only their owners can and, as noted above, they may find it more profitable to tolerate (or even encourage) pollution than sue. Given that non-owners cannot sue as they are not directly harmed, the fate of the planet will rest in the hands of the property-owning class and so the majority are effectively dispossessed of any say over their environment beyond  what their money can buy. Transforming ecological concerns into money  ensures a monopoly by the wealthy few:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "In other words, the environment is assumed to be something that can be 'valued,' in a similar way that everything else is assigned a value within the market economy.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"However, apart from the fact that there is no way to put an  'objective' value on most of the elements that constitute the  environment (since they affect a subjective par excellence factor, i.e. the quality of life), the solution suggested . . . implies the extension of the marketisation process to the environment  itself. In other words, it implies the assignment of a market  value to the environment . . . so that the effects of growth  onto it are 'internalised' . . . The outcome of such a process is easily predictable: the environment will either be put under the control of the economic elites that control the market  economy (in case an actual market value be assigned to it) or the state (in case an imputed value is only possible). In  either case, not only the arrest of the ecological damage is  -- at least -- doubtful, but the control over Nature by elites who aim to dominate it -- using 'green' prescriptions this time -- is perpetuated."</i> [Takis Fotopoulous, <i>"Development or  Democracy?"</i>, pp. 57-92, <b>Society and Nature</b>, No. 7, pp. 79-80]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>Another key problem with using private property in regard to environmental  issues is that they are almost always reactive, almost never proactive.  Thus the pollution needs to have occurred before court actions are taken as strict liability generally provides after-the-fact compensation for  injuries received. If someone does successfully sue for damages, the money  received can hardly replace an individual or species or eco-system. At best,  it could be argued that the threat of being sued will stop environmentally  damaging activities but there is little evidence that this works. If a  company concludes that the damages incurred by court action is less than  the potential profits to be made, then they will tolerate the possibility  of court action (particularly if they feel that potential victims do not  have the time or resources available to sue). This kind of decision was  most infamously done by General Motors when it designed its Malibu car.  The company estimated that the cost of court awarded damages per car was  less than ensuring that the car did not explode during certain kinds of  collusion and so allowed people to die in fuel-fed fires rather than  alter the design. Unfortunately for GM, the jury was horrified (on appeal,  the damages were substantially reduced). [Joel Bakan, <b>The Corporation</b>,  pp. 61-5]</p>
<p>So this means that companies seeking to maximise profits have an incentive to cut safety costs on the assumption that the risk of so doing will be sufficiently low to make it worthwhile and that any profits generated will more than cover the costs of any trial and damages imposed. As eco-anarchist David Watson noted in regards to the Prudhoe Bay disaster, it <i>"should go without saying that Exxon and its allies don't try their  best to protect the environment or human health. Capitalist institutions  produce to accumulate power and wealth, not for any social good. Predictably,  in order to cut costs, Exxon steadily dismantled what emergency safeguards it had throughout the 1980s, pointing to environmental studies showing a  major spill as so unlikely that preparation was unnecessary. So when the  inevitable came crashing down, the response was complete impotence and  negligence."</i> [<b>Against the Megamachine</b>, p. 57] As such, it cannot be stressed too much that the only reason companies act any different (if and  when they do) is because outside agitators -- people who understand and  cared about the planet and people more than they did about company profits  -- eventually forced them to.</p>
<p>So given all this, it is clear that privatising nature is no guarantee that environmental problems will be reduced. In fact, it is more likely to have the opposite effect. Even its own advocates suggest that their  solution may produce <b>more</b> pollution than the current system of state  regulation. Terry L. Anderson and Donald R. Leal put it this way:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "If markets produce 'too little' clean water because dischargers do not have to pay for its use, then political solutions are equally likely to produce 'too much' clean water because those who enjoy the benefits do not pay the cost . . . Just as pollution externalities can generate too much dirty air, political externalities can generate too much water storage, clear-cutting, wilderness, or water quality . . . Free market environmentalism emphasises the importance of market process in determining optimal amounts of resource use."</i> [<b>Free Market Environmentalism</b>, p. 23]
</p></blockquote>
<p>What kind of environmentalism considers the possibility of "too much" clean air and water? This means, ironically, that from the perspective  of free-market "environmentalism" that certain ecological features may be  over-protected as a result of the influence of non-economic goals and  priorities. Given that this model is proposed by many corporate funded think tanks, it is more than likely that their sponsors think there is  "too much" clean air and water, "too much" wilderness and "too much"  environmental goods. In other words, the "optimal" level of pollution is currently too low as it doubtful that corporations are seeking to increase their costs of production by internalising even more  externalities.</p>
<p>Equally, we can be sure that "too much" pollution <i>"is where the company  polluting the water has to pay too much to clean up the mess they make. It  involves a judgement that costs to the company are somehow synonymous with  costs to the community and therefore can be weighed against benefits to the community."</i> Such measures <i>"grant the highest decision-making power over  environmental quality to those who currently make production decisions. A  market system gives power to those most able to pay. Corporations and firms, rather than citizens or environmentalists, will have the choice about whether to pollute (and pay the charges or buy credits to do so)."</i> [Sharon Beder, <b>Global Spin</b>, p. 104]</p>
<p>The surreal notion of "too much" clean environment does indicate another  key problem with this approach, namely its confusion of need and demand  with <b>effective</b> demand. The fact is that people may desire a clean  environment, but they may not be able to afford to pay for it on the market.  In a similar way, there can be "too much" food while people are starving to  death simply because people cannot afford to pay for it (there is no effective  demand for food, but an obvious pressing need). Much the same can be said of  environment goods. A lack of demand for a resource today does <b>not</b> mean  it is not valued by individuals nor does it mean that it will not be valued  in the future. However, in the short-term focus produced by the market such  goods will be long-gone, replaced by more profitable investments.</p>
<p>The underlying assumption is that a clean environment is a luxury which  we must purchase from property owners rather than a right we have as  human beings. Even if we assume the flawed concept of self-ownership, the principle upon which defenders of capitalism tend to justify their system, the principle should be that our ownership rights in our bodies  excludes it being harmed by the actions of others. In other words, a clean environment should be a basic right for all. Privatising the  environment goes directly against this basic ecological insight.</p>
<p>The state's environmental record <b>has</b> often been terrible, particularly  as its bureaucrats have been influenced by private interest groups when  formulating and implementing environmental policies. The state is  far more likely to be "captured" by capitalist interests than by  environmental groups or even the general community. Moreover, its  bureaucrats have all too often tended to weight the costs and benefits  of specific projects in such a way as to ensure that any really desired  ones will go ahead, regardless of what local people want or what the  environmental impact will really be. Such projects, needless to say, will  almost always have powerful economic interests behind them and will seek  to ensure that "development" which fosters economic growth is pursued.  This should be unsurprising. If we assume, as "market advocates" do,  that state officials seek to further their own interests then classes  with the most economic wealth are most likely to be able to do that  the best. That the state will reflect the interests of those with most  private property and marginalise the property-less should, therefore,  come as no surprise.</p>
<p>Yet the state is not immune to social pressure from the general public  or the reality of environmental degradation. This is proved, in its  own way, by the rise of corporate PR, lobbying and think-tanks into  multi-million pound industries. So while the supporters of the market  stress its ability to change in the face of consumer demand, their  view of the alternatives is extremely static and narrow. They fail, unsurprisingly, to consider the possibility of alternative forms of  social organisation. Moreover, they also fail to mention that popular  struggles can influence the state by means of direct action. For them,  state officials will always pursue their own private interests,  irrespective of popular pressures and social struggles (or, for that matter, the impact of corporate lobbying). While it is possible that  the state will favour specific interests and policies, it does not  mean that it cannot be forced to consider wider ones by the general  public (until such time as it can be abolished, of course).</p>
<p>As we discussed in <a href="secD1.html#secd15">section D.1.5</a>, the  fact the state can be pressured  by the general public is precisely why certain of its secondary functions  have been under attack by corporations and the wealthy (a task which their  well-funded think-tanls provide the rationales for). If all this is the case  (and it is), then why expect cutting out the middle-person by privatising  nature to improve matters? By its own logic, therefore, privatising nature  is hardly going to produce a better environment as it is unlikely that  corporations would fund policies which would result in more costs for themselves and less access to valuable natural resources. As free market environmentalism is premised on economic solutions to ecological problems and assumes that economic agents will act in ways which maximise their own benefit, such an obvious conclusion should come naturally to its  advocates. For some reason, it does not.</p>
<p>Ultimately, privatising nature rests on the ridiculous notion that a clean  environment is a privilege which we must buy rather than a right. Under "free  market environmentalism" private property is assumed to be the fundamental right  while there is no right to a clean and sustainable environment. In other  words, the interests of property owners are considered the most important  factor and the rest of us are left with the possibility of asking them for  certain environmental goods which they may supply if they make a profit  from so doing. This prioritisation and categorisation is by no means obvious  and uncontroversial. Surely the right to a clean and liveable environment is more fundamental than those associated with property? If we assume this then the reduction of pollution, soil erosion, and so forth  are not goods for which we must pay but rather rights to which we  are entitled. In other words, protecting species and ecosystem as well  as preventing avoidable deaths and illnesses are fundamental issues  which simply transcend the market. Being asked to put a price on nature  and people is, at best, meaningless, or, at worse, degrading. It suggests that the person simply does not understand why these things are important.</p>
<p>But why should we be surprised? After all, private property bases itself  on the notion that we must buy access to land and other resources required  for a fully human life. Why should a clean environment and a healthy body be any different? Yet again, we see the derived rights (namely private  property) trumping the fundamental base right (namely the right of  self-ownership which should automatically exclude harm by pollution).  That this happens so consistently should not come as too great a  surprise, given that the theory was invented to justify the appropriation  of the fruits of the worker's labour by the property owner (see  <a href="secB4.html#secb42">section B.4.2</a>). Why  should we be surprised that this is now being used to  appropriate the rights of individuals to a clean environment and turn it into yet another means of expropriating them from their birthrights?</p>
<h2><a name="sece32">E.3.2 How does economic power contribute to the ecological crisis?</a></h2>
<p>So far in this section we have discussed why markets fail to allocate  environmental resources. This is due to information blocks and costs,  lack of fully internalised prices (externalities) and the existence  of public goods. Individual choices are shaped by the information  available to them about the consequences of their actions, and the  price mechanism blocks essential aspects of this and so information  is usually partial at best within the market. Worse, it is usually distorted by advertising and the media as well as corporate and  government spin and PR. Local knowledge is undermined by market  power, leading to unsustainable practices to reap maximum short  term profits. Profits as the only decision making criteria also leads  to environmental destruction as something which may be ecologically essential may not be economically viable. All this means that the  price of a good cannot indicate its environmental impact and so that  market failure is pervasive in the environmental area. Moreover,  capitalism is as unlikely to produce their fair distribution of environmental goods any more than any other good or resource due  to differences in income and so demand (particularly as it takes  the existing distribution of wealth as the starting point). The reality  of our environmental problems provides ample evidence for this  analysis.</p>
<p>During this discussion we have touched upon another key issue, namely how wealth can affect how environmental and other externalities are  produced and dealt with in a capitalist system. Here we extend our  critique by addressed an issue we have deliberately ignored until now, namely the distribution and wealth and its resulting economic  power. The importance of this factor cannot be stressed too much, as "market advocates" at best downplay it or, at worse, ignore it or deny it exists. However, it plays the same role in environmental  matters as it does in, say, evaluating individual freedom within  capitalism. Once we factor in economic power the obvious conclusion is the market based solutions to the environment will result in, as  with freedom, people selling it simply to survive under capitalism (as we discussed in <a href="secB4.html">section B.4</a>, for example).</p>
<p>It could be argued that strictly enforcing property rights so that polluters can be sued for any damages made will solve the problem of externalities. If someone suffered pollution damage on their  property which they had not consented to then they could issue  a lawsuit in order to get the polluter to pay compensation for the damage they have done. This could force polluters to internalise  the costs of pollution and so the threat of lawsuits can be used as an incentive to avoid polluting others.</p>
<p>While this approach could be considered as <b>part</b> of any solution to environmental problems under capitalism, the sad fact is it ignores  the realities of the capitalist economy.  The key phrase here is "not  consented to" as it means that pollution would be fine if the others  agree to it (in return, say, for money). This has obvious implications for the ability of capitalism to reduce pollution. For just as working  class people "consent" to hierarchy within the workplace in return for  access to the means of life, so to would they "consent" to pollution. In  other words, the notion that pollution can be stopped by means of private property and lawsuits ignores the issue of class and economic  inequality. Once these are factored in, it soon becomes clear that  people may put up with externalities imposed upon them simply because of economic necessity and the pressure big business can inflict.</p>
<p>The first area to discuss is inequalities in wealth and income. Not all economic actors have equal resources. Corporations and the wealthy have far greater resources at their disposal and can spend millions of pounds in producing PR and advertising (propaganda), fighting court cases, influencing the political process, funding  "experts" and think-tanks, and, if need be, fighting strikes and protests. Companies can use <i>"a mix of cover-up, publicity campaigns  and legal manoeuvres to continue operations unimpeded."</i> They can go  to court to try an <i>"block more stringent pollution controls."</i> [David  Watson, <b>Against the Megamachine</b>, p. 56] Also while, in principle,  the legal system offers equal protection to all in reality, wealthy  firms and individuals have more resources than members of the general  public. This means that they can employ large numbers of lawyers and  draw out litigation procedures for years, if not decades.</p>
<p>This can be seen around us today. Unsurprisingly, the groups which bear  a disproportionate share of environmental burdens are the poorest ones.  Those at the bottom of the social hierarchy have less resources available to fight for their rights. They may not be aware of their rights in  specific situations and not organised enough to resist. This, of course, explains why companies spend so much time attacking unions and other  forms of collective organisation which change that situation. Moreover as well as being less willing to sue, those on lower income may be more  willing to be bought-off due to their economic situation. After all,  tolerating pollution in return for some money is more tempting when  you are struggling to make ends meet.</p>
<p>Then there is the issue of effective demand. Simply put, allocation of resources on the market is based on money and not need. If more money can be made in, say, meeting the consumption demands of the west rather than the needs of local people then the market will "efficiently" allocate resources away from the latter to the former regardless of the social and ecological impact. Take the example of Biofuels which have been presented by some as a  means of fuelling cars in a less environmentally destructive way. Yet this brings people and cars into direct competition over the most "efficient" (i.e. most profitable) use of land. Unfortunately, effective demand is on the side of cars as their owners usually live in the developed countries. This leads to a situation where land is turned from producing food to producing biofuels, the net effect of which is to reduce supply of food,  increase its price and so produce an increased likelihood of starvation. It also gives more economic incentive to destroy rainforests and other fragile eco-systems in order to produce more biofuel for the market.</p>
<p>Green socialist John O'Neill simply states the obvious:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "[The] treatment of efficiency as if it were logically independent of distribution is at best misleading, for the determination of efficiency already presupposes a given distribution of rights . . . [A specific outcome] is always relative to an initial starting point . . . If property rights are changed so also is what is efficient. Hence, the opposition between distributional and efficiency criteria is misleading. Existing costs and benefits themselves are the product of a given distribution of property rights. Since costs are not independent of rights they cannot  guide the allocation of rights. Different initial distributions entail differences in whose preferences are to count. Environmental conflicts are often about who has rights to environment goods, and  hence who is to bear the costs and who is to bear the benefits  . . . Hence, environmental policy and resource decision-making  cannot avoid making normative choices which include questions of resource distribution and the relationships between conflicting rights claims . . . The monetary value of a 'negative externality'  depends on social institutions and distributional conflicts --  willing to pay measures, actual or hypothetical, consider  preferences of the higher income groups [as] more important than  those of lower ones. If the people damaged are poor, the monetary  measure of the cost of damage will be lower -- 'the poor sell  cheap.'"</i> [<b>Markets, Deliberation and Environment</b>, pp. 58-9]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Economic power also impacts on the types of contracts people make. It does  not take too much imagination to envision the possibility that companies  may make signing waivers that release it from liability a condition for  working there. This could mean, for example, a firm would invest (or  threaten to move production) only on condition that the local community  and its workers sign a form waiving the firm of any responsibility for  damages that may result from working there or from its production process.  In the face of economic necessity, the workers may be desperate enough to take the jobs and sign the waivers. The same would be the case for local communities, who tolerate the environmental destruction they are subjected to simply to ensure that their economy remains viable. This already happens,  with some companies including a clause in their contracts which states the  employee cannot join a union.</p>
<p>Then there is the threat of legal action by companies. <i>"Every year,"</i>  records green Sharon Beder, <i>"thousands of Americans are sued for speaking out against governments and corporations. Multi-million dollar law suits are being filed against individual citizens and groups for circulating petitions, writing to public officials, speaking at,  or even just attending, public meetings, organising a boycott and  engaging in peaceful demonstrations."</i> This trend has spread to  other countries and the intent is the same: to silence opposition and undermine campaigns. This tactic is called a SLAPP (for <i><b>"Strategic Lawsuits Against Public Participation"</b></i>) and is a civil court action which does not seek to win compensation but rather aims <i>"to harass,  intimidate and distract their opponents . . . They win the political battle, even when they lose the court case, if their victims and those associated with them stop speaking out against them."</i> This  is an example of economic power at work, for the cost to a firm is  just part of doing business but could bankrupt an individual or  environmental organisation. In this way <i>"the legal system best serves those who have large financial resources at their disposal"</i> as such cases take <i>"an average of three years to be settled, and even if the person sued wins, can cost tens of thousands of  dollars in legal fees. Emotional stress, disillusionment, diversion of time and energy, and even divisions within families, communities and groups can also result."</i> [<b>Global Spin</b>, pp. 63-7]</p>
<p>A SLAPP usually deters those already involved from continuing to freely  participate in debate and protest as well as deterring others from joining  in. The threat of a court case in the face of economic power usually  ensures that SLAPPS do not go to trial and so its objective of scaring off  potential opponents usually works quickly. The reason can be seen from  the one case in which a SLAPP backfired, namely the McLibel trial. After successfully forcing apologies from major UK media outlets like the BBC, Channel 4 and the Guardian by threatening legal action for critical reporting of the company, McDonald's turned its attention to the small eco-anarchist group London Greenpeace (which is not affiliated with Greenpeace International). This group had produced a leaflet called  <i>"What's Wrong with McDonald's"</i> and the company sent spies to its meetings to identify people to sue. Two of the anarchists refused to be intimidated and called McDonald's bluff. Representing themselves in court, the two unemployed activists started the longest trial in UK history. After three years and a cost of around £10 million, the trial judge found  that some of the claims were untrue (significantly, McDonald's had  successfully petitioned the judge not to have a jury for the case,  arguing that the issues were too complex for the public to understand). While the case was a public relations disaster for the company, McDonald's  keeps going as before using the working practices exposed in the trial and  remains one of the world's largest corporations confident that few people  would have the time and resources to fight SLAPPs (although the corporation  may now think twice before suing anarchists!).</p>
<p>Furthermore, companies are known to gather lists of known "trouble-makers"  These "black lists" of people who could cause companies "trouble" (i.e.,  by union organising or suing employers over "property rights" issues)  would often ensure employee "loyalty," particularly if new jobs need  references. Under wage labour, causing one's employer "problems" can  make one's current and future position difficult. Being black-listed  would mean no job, no wages, and little chance of being re-employed.  This would be the result of continually suing in defence of one's  property rights -- assuming, of course, that one had the time and money  necessary to sue in the first place. Hence working-class people are a  weak position to defend their rights under capitalism due to the power  of employers both within and without the workplace. All these are strong  incentives <b>not</b> to rock the boat, particularly if employees have signed  a contract ensuring that they will be fired if they discuss company  business with others (lawyers, unions, media, etc.).</p>
<p>Economic power producing terrible contracts does not affect just labour, it also effects smaller capitalists as well. As we discussed in  <a href="secC4.html">section C.4</a>, rather than operating "efficiently" to allocate resources within  perfect competition any real capitalist market is dominated by a small  group of big companies who make increased profits at the expense of their smaller rivals. This is achieved, in part, because their size gives such  firms significant influence in the market, forcing smaller companies out of business or into making concessions to get and maintain contracts.</p>
<p>The negative environmental impact of such a process should be obvious. For example, economic power places immense pressures towards monoculture  in agriculture. In the UK the market is dominated by a few big supermarkets. Their suppliers are expected to produce fruits and vegetables which meet the requirements of the supermarkets in terms of standardised products  which are easy to transport and store. The large-scale nature of the  operations ensure that farmers across Britain (indeed, the world) have  to turn their farms into suppliers of these standardised goods and so the natural diversity of nature is systematically replaced by a few  strains of specific fruits and vegetables over which the consumer can pick. Monopolisation of markets results in the monoculture of nature.</p>
<p>This process is at work in all capitalist nations. In American, for example, the <i>"centralised purchasing decisions of the large restaurant chains and their demand for standardised  products have given a handful  of corporations an unprecedented degree of power over the nation's food  supply . . . obliterating regional differences, and spreading identical  stores throughout the country . . . The key to a successful franchise  . . . can be expressed in one world: 'uniformity.'"</i> This has resulted in the industrialisation of food production, with the <i>"fast food chains  now stand[ing] atop a huge food-industrial complex that has gained control  of American agriculture . . . large multinationals . . . dominate one  commodity market after another . . . The fast food chain's vast  purchasing power and their demand for a uniform product have encouraged  fundamental changes in how cattle are raised, slaughter, and processed  into ground beef. These changes have made meatpacking . . . into the most dangerous job in the United States . . . And the same meat industry practices that endanger these workers have facilitated the introduction of deadly pathogens . . . into America's hamburger meat."</i> [Eric Schlosser,  <b>Fast Food Nation</b>, p. 5 and pp. 8-9]</p>
<p>Award winning journalist Eric Schlosser has presented an excellent insight  in this centralised and concentrated food-industrial complex in his book <b>Fast Food Nation</b>. Schlosser, of course, is not alone in documenting the  fundamentally anti-ecological nature of the capitalism and how an alienated  society has created an alienated means of feeding itself. As a non-anarchist, he does fail to drawn the obvious conclusion (namely abolish capitalism) but  his book does present a good overview of the nature of the processed at work and what drives them. Capitalism has created a world where even the smell and  taste of food is mass produced as the industrialisation of agriculture and food  processing has lead to the product (it is hard to call it food) becoming bland  and tasteless and so chemicals are used to counteract the effects of producing  it on such a scale. It is standardised food for a standardised society.  As he memorably notes: <i>"Millions of . . . people at that very moment were  standing at the same counter, ordering the same food from the same menu,  food that tasted everywhere the same."</i> The Orwellian world of modern corporate  capitalism is seen in all its glory. A world in which the industry group formed  to combat Occupational Safety and Health Administration regulation is called  <i>"Alliance for Workplace Safety"</i> and where the processed food's taste has  to have the correct <i>"mouthfeel."</i>  Unsurprisingly, the executives of these companies talk about <i>"the very essence of freedom"</i> and yet their corporation's  <i>"first commandant is that only production counts . . . The employee's duty  is to follow orders. Period."</i> In this irrational world, technology will solve  all our problems, even the ones it generates itself.  For example, faced with  the serious health problems generated by the industrialisation of meat processing,  the meatpacking industry advocated yet more technology to "solve" the problems  caused by the existing technology. Rather than focusing on the primary causes  of meat contamination, they proposed irradiating food. Of course the firms  involved want to replace the word <i>"irradiation"</i> with the phrase <i>"cold  pasteurisation"</i> due to the public being unhappy with the idea of their  food being subject to radiation.</p>
<p>All this is achievable due to the economic power of fewer and fewer firms imposing costs onto their workers, their customers and, ultimately, the  planet.</p>
<p>The next obvious factor associated with economic power are the pressures  associated with capital markets and mobility. Investors and capitalists  are always seeking the maximum return and given a choice between lower  profits due to greater environmental regulation and higher profits due  to no such laws, the preferred option will hardly need explaining. After  all, the investor is usually concerned with the returns they get in their investment, <b>not</b> in its physical condition nor in the overall environmental  state of the planet (which is someone else's concern). This means that  investors and companies interest is in moving their capital to areas which  return most money, not which have the best environmental impact and legacy.  Thus the mobility of capital has to be taken into account. This is an  important weapon  in ensuring that the agenda of business is untroubled by  social concerns and environmental issues. After all, if the owners and  managers of capital consider that a state's environmental laws too  restrictive then it can simply shift investments to states with a more  favourable business climate. This creates significant pressures on  communities to minimise environmental protection both in order to retain  existing business and attract new ones.</p>
<p>Let us assume that a company is polluting a local area. It is usually the  case that capitalist owners rarely live near the workplaces they own, unlike workers and their families. This means that the decision makers  do not have to live with the consequences of their decisions. The "free  market" capitalist argument would be, again, that those affected by the pollution would sue the company. We will assume that concentrations of wealth have little or no effect on the social system (which is a <b>highly</b> unlikely assumption, but never mind). Surely, if local people did successfully sue, the company would be harmed economically -- directly,  in terms of the cost of the judgement, indirectly in terms of having  to implement new, eco-friendly processes. Hence the company would be handicapped in competition, and this would have obvious consequences  for the local (and wider) economy.</p>
<p>This gives the company an incentive to simply move to an area that  would tolerate the pollution if it were sued or even threatened with a lawsuit. Not only would existing capital move, but fresh capital  would not invest in an area where people stand up for their rights.  This -- the natural result of economic power -- would be a "big stick"  over the heads of the local community. And when combined with the costs  and difficulties in taking a large company to court, it would make suing an unlikely option for most people. That such a result would occur can be inferred from history, where we see that multinational firms have moved production to countries with little or no pollution laws and that court cases take years, if not decades, to process.</p>
<p>This is the current situation on the international market, where there is  competition in terms of environment laws. Unsurprisingly, industry tends  to move to countries which tolerate high levels of pollution (usually  because of authoritarian governments which, like the capitalists themselves,  simply ignore the wishes of the general population). Thus we have a market  in pollution laws which, unsurprisingly, supplies the ability to pollute  to meet the demand for it. This means that developing countries <i>"are  nothing but a dumping ground and pool of cheap labour for capitalist  corporations. Obsolete technology is shipped there along with the  production of chemicals, medicines and other products banned in the  developed world. Labour is cheap, there are few if any safety standards,  and costs are cut. But the formula of cost-benefit still stands: the  costs are simply borne by others, by the victims of Union Carbide,  Dow, and Standard Oil."</i> [David Watson, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 44]  This, it should be noted, makes perfect economic sense. If an accident  happened and the poor actually manage to successfully sue the company, any  payments will reflect their lost of earnings (i.e., not very much).</p>
<p>As such, there are other strong economic reasons for doing this kind of pollution exporting. You can estimate the value of production lost because  of ecological damage and the value of earnings lost through its related  health problems as well as health care costs. This makes it more likely  that polluting industries will move to low-income areas or countries  where the costs of pollution are correspondingly less (particularly  compared to the profits made in selling the products in high-income areas).  Rising incomes makes such goods as safety, health and the environment  more valuable as the value of life is, for working people, based on  their wages. Therefore, we would expect pollution to be valued less  when working class people are affected by it. In other words, toxic  dumps will tend to cluster around poorer areas as the costs of paying for  the harm done will be much less. The same logic underlies the arguments of those who suggest that Third World countries should be dumping grounds for  toxic industrial wastes since life is cheap there</p>
<p>This was seen in early 1992 when a memo that went out under the name of  the then chief economist of the World Bank, Lawrence Summers, was leaked  to the press. Discussing the issue of <i>"dirty"</i> Industries, the memo  argued that the World Bank should <i>"be encouraging MORE migration  of the dirty industries"</i> to Less Developed Countries and provided three  reasons. Firstly, the <i>"measurements of the costs of health impairing  pollution depends on the foregone earnings from increased morbidity  and mortality"</i> and so <i>"pollution should be done in the country with  the lowest cost, which will be the country with the lowest wages."</i> Secondly, <i>"that under-populated countries in Africa are vastly  UNDER-polluted, their air quality is probably vastly inefficiently  low compared to Los Angeles or Mexico City."</i> Thirdly, the <i>"demand for  a clean environment for aesthetic and health reasons is likely to have  very high income elasticity."</i> Concern over pollution related illness would be higher in a country where more children survive to get them.  <i>"Also, much of the concern over industrial atmosphere discharge is  about visibility impairing particulates . . . Clearly trade in goods  that embody aesthetic pollution concerns could be welfare enhancing.  While production is mobile the consumption of pretty air is a  non-tradable."</i> The memo notes <i>"the economic logic behind dumping a  load of toxic waste in the lowest wage country is impeccable and we  should face up to that"</i> and ends by stating that the <i>"problem with  the arguments against all of these proposals for more pollution"</i> in  the third world <i>"could be turned around and used more or less  effectively against every Bank proposal for liberalisation."</i> [<b>The Economist</b>, 08/02/1992]</p>
<p>While Summers accepted the criticism for the memo, it was actually  written by Lant Pritchett, a prominent economist at the Bank.  Summers claimed he was being ironic and provocative. <b>The Economist</b>,  unsurprisingly, stated <i>"his economics was hard to answer"</i> while  criticising the language used. This was because clean growth may slower than allowing pollution to occur and this would stop <i>"helping  millions of people in the third world to escape their poverty."</i>  [15/02/1992] So not only is poisoning the poor with pollution is  economically correct, it is in fact required by morality. Ignoring  the false assumption that growth, any kind of growth, always benefits  the poor and the utter contempt shown for both those poor themselves and our environment what we have here is the cold logic that drives  economic power to move location to maintain its right to pollute our  common environment. Economically, it is perfectly logical but, in fact,  totally insane (this  helps explain why making people "think like an  economist" takes so many years of indoctrination within university  walls and why so few achieve it).</p>
<p>Economic power works in other ways as well. A classic example of this at work can be seen from the systematic destruction of public transport  systems in America from the 1930s onwards (see David St. Clair's <b>The  Motorization of American Cities</b> for a well-researched account of this). These systems were deliberately bought by automotive (General Motors),  oil, and tire corporations in order to eliminate a less costly (both  economically <b>and</b> ecologically) competitor to the automobile. This  was done purely to maximise sales and profits for the companies involved  yet it transformed the way of life in scores of cities across America. It  is doubtful that if environmental concerns had been considered important  at the time that they would have stopped this from happening. This means  that individual consumption decisions will be made within an market whose  options can be limited simply by a large company buying out and destroying  alternatives.</p>
<p>Then there is the issue of economic power in the media. This is well understood  by corporations, who fund PR, think-tanks and "experts" to counteract environmental  activism and deny, for example, that humans are contributing to global warming.  Thus we have the strange position that only Americans think that there is a  debate on the causes of global warming rather than a scientific consensus. The actions of corporate funded "experts" and PR have ensured <b>that</b> particular  outcome. As Sharon Beder recounts in her book <b>Global Spin: The Corporate Assault on Environmentalism</b>, a large amount of money is being spent on  number sophisticated techniques to change the way people think about the  environment, what causes the problems we face and what we can and should do about it. Compared to the resources of environmental and green organisations, it is unsurprising that this elaborate multi-billion pound industry has poisoned  public debate on such a key issue for the future of humanity by propaganda and  dis-information.</p>
<p>Having substantial resources available means that the media can be used to further an anti-green agenda and dominate the debate (at least for a while). Take, as an example, <b>The Skeptical Environmentalist</b>, a book  by Bjørn Lomborg (a political scientist and professor of statistics at  the University of Aarhus in Denmark). When it was published in 2001, it  caused a sensation with its claims that scientists and environmental  organisations were making, at best, exaggerated and, at worse, false  claims about the world's environmental problems. His conclusion was  panglossian in nature, namely that there was not that much to worry  about and we can continue as we are. That, of course, was music to the  ears of those actively destroying the environment as it reduces the likelihood that any attempt will be made to stop them.</p>
<p>Unsurprisingly, the book was heavily promoted by the usual suspects and,  as a result received significant attention from the media. However, the  <b>extremely</b> critical reviews and critiques it subsequently produced  from expert scientists on the issues Lomborg discussed were less  prominently reviewed in the media, if at all. That critics of the book  argued that it was hardly an example of good science based on objectivity,  understanding of the underlying concepts, appropriate statistical  methods and careful peer review goes without saying. Sadly, the fact that numerous experts in the fields Lomborg discussed showed that his  book was seriously flawed, misused data and statistics and marred by  flawed logic and hidden value judgements was not given anything like the  same coverage even though this information is far more important in terms  of shaping public perception. Such works and their orchestrated media blitz provides those with a vested interest in the status quo with  arguments that they should be allowed to continue their anti-environmental  activities and agenda. Moreover, it takes up the valuable time of those  experts who have to debunk the claims rather than do the research needed  to understand the ecological problems we face and propose possible solutions.</p>
<p>As well as spin and propaganda aimed at adults, companies are increasingly  funding children's education. This development implies obvious limitations  on the power of education to solve ecological problems. Companies will  hardly provide teaching materials or fund schools which educate their  pupils on the <b>real</b> causes of ecological problems. Unsurprisingly, a 1998 study in the US by the Consumers Union found that 80% of teaching material provided by companies was biased and provided students with incomplete or slanted information that favoured its sponsor's products and views [Schlosser, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 55] The more dependent a school is on corporate funds, the less likely it will be to teach its students the necessity to question the motivations and activities of business. That business will not fund education which it perceives as anti-business should go without saying. As Sharon Beder summarises, <i>"the infiltration of school curricula through banning some texts and offering corporate-based curriculum material and lesson plans in their place can conflict with educational objectives, and also with the attainment of an undistorted understanding of environmental problems."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 172-3]</p>
<p>This indicates the real problem of purely "educational" approaches to solving the ecological crisis, namely that the ruling elite controls  education (either directly or indirectly). This is to be expected, as any capitalist elite must control education because it is an essential indoctrination tool needed to promote capitalist values and to train a large population of future wage-slaves in the proper habits of obedience to authority. Thus capitalists cannot afford to lose control of the educational system. And this means that such schools will not teach students what is really necessary to avoid ecological disaster: namely the dismantling of capitalism itself. And we may add, alternative schools (organised by libertarian unions and other associations) which used libertarian education to produce anarchists would hardly be favoured by companies and so be effectively black-listed - a real deterrent to their spreading through society. Why would a capitalist company employ a graduate of a school who would make trouble for them once employed  as their wage slave?</p>
<p>Finally, needless to say, the combined wealth of corporations and the rich  outweighs that of even the best funded environmental group or organisation (or even all of them put together). This means that the idea of such groups buying, say, rainforest is unlikely to succeed as they simply do not have  the resources needed -- they will be outbid by those who wish to develop  wilderness regions. This is particularly the case once we accept the  framework of economic self-interest assumed by market theory. This implies  that organisations aiming to increase the income of individual's will  be better funded than those whose aim is to preserve the environment for  future generations. As recent developments show, companies can and do use that superior resources to wage a war for hearts and minds in all aspects of society, staring in the schoolroom. Luckily no amount of spin can nullify reality or the spirit of freedom and so this propaganda war will continue as long as capitalism does.</p>
<p>In summary, market solutions to environmental problems under capitalism will always suffer from the fact that real markets are marked by economic inequalities and power.</p>
<h2><a name="sece33">E.3.3 Can capitalism's focus on short-term profitability  deal with the ecological crisis?</a></h2>
<p>No a word, no. This is another key problem associated with capitalism's  ability to deal with the ecological crisis it helps create. Due to the nature of the market, firms are forced to focus on short-term profitability rather than long-term survival. This makes sense. If a company does not make money now, it will not be around later.</p>
<p>This, obviously, drives the creation of "externalities" discussed  in previous sections. Harmful environmental effects such as pollution,  global warming, ozone depletion, and destruction of wildlife habitat  are not counted as "costs of production" in standard methods of accounting  because they are borne by everyone in the society. This gives companies a  strong incentive to ignore such costs as competition forces firms to  cut as many costs as possible in order to boost short-term profits.</p>
<p>To give an obvious example, if a firm has to decide between installing a piece of costly equipment which reduces its pollution and continuing as it currently is, then it is more likely to do the latter. If the firm <b>does</b> invest then its costs are increased and it will lose its  competitive edge compared to its rivals who do not make a similar  investment. The "rational" decision is, therefore, not to invest, particularly if by externalising costs it can increase its profits or market  share by cutting prices. In other words, the market rewards the polluters  and this is a powerful incentive to maximise such activities. The market,  in other words, provides incentives to firms to produce externalities  as part their drive for short-term profitability. While this is rational from the firm's position, it is collectively irrational as the planet's  ecology is harmed.</p>
<p>The short-term perspective can also be seen by the tendency of firms to  under-invest in developing risky new technologies. This is because basic  research which may take years, if not decades, to develop and most  companies are unwilling to take on that burden. Unsurprisingly, most  advanced capitalist countries see such work funded by the state (as we  noted in <a href="secD8.html">section D.8</a>, over  50% of total R&amp;D funding has been provided  by the federal state in the USA). Moreover, the state has provided  markets for such products until such time as markets have appeared for  them in the commercial sector. Thus capitalism, by itself, will tend to  under-invest in long term projects:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "in a competitive system you do <b>short-term planning only</b> . . .  Let's take corporate managers, where there's no real confusion about what they're doing. They are maximising profit and market share in the short term. In fact, if they were not to do that, they would no  longer exist. Let's be concrete. Suppose that some automobile company, say General Motors, decides to devote their resources to planning for something that will be profitable ten years from now. Suppose that's where they divert their resources: they want to think in some long-term conception of market dominance. Their rivals are going to maximising profit and power in the short term, and they're going to take over the market, and General Motors won't be in business. That's true for the owners and also for the managers. The managers want to stay managers. They can fight off hostile take-over bids, they can keep from being replaced, as long as they contribute to  short-term profitability. As a result, long-term considerations  are rarely considered in competitive systems."</i> [Noam Chomsky,  <b>Language and Politics</b>, p. 598]
</p></blockquote>
<p>This does not mean that firms will not look into future products nor do research and development. Many do (particularly if helped by the state). Nor does it imply that some industries do not have a longer-term  perspective. It simply shows that such activity is not the normal state of affairs. Moreover, any such "long-term" perspective is rarely more  than a decade while an ecological perspective demands much more than this. This also applies to agriculture, which is increasingly being turned  into agribusiness as small farmers are being driven out of business. Short-termism means that progress in agriculture is whatever increases  the current yield of a crop even if means destroying the sources of  fertility in the long run in order to maintain current fertility by  adding more and more chemicals (which run off into rivers, seep into  the water table and end up in the food itself.</p>
<p>This kind of irrational short-term behaviour also afflicts capital markets as well. The process works in the same way Chomsky highlights.  Suppose there are 3 companies, X, Y, and Z and suppose that company X  invests in the project of developing a non-polluting technology within  ten years. At the same time its competitors, Y and Z, will be putting  their resources into increasing profits and market share in the coming  days and months and over the next year. During that period, company X  will be unable to attract enough capital from investors to carry out  its plans, since investors will flock to the companies that are most  immediately profitable. This means that the default position under  capitalism is that the company (or country) with the lowest standards  enjoys a competitive advantage, and drags down the standards of other  companies (or countries). Sometimes, though, capital markets experience  irrational bubbles. During the dot.com boom of the 1990s, investors did  plough money into internet start-ups and losses were tolerated for a  few years in the expectation of high profits in the near future. When  that did not happen, the stock market crashed and investors turned  away from that market in droves. If something similar happened to  eco-technologies, the subsequent aftermath may mean that funding  essential for redressing our interaction with the environment would  not be forthcoming until the memories of the crash had disappeared in the next bubble frenzy.</p>
<p>Besides, thanks to compound interest benefits far in the future have a very small present value. If $1 were left in a bank at 5% annual  interest, it would be worth more than $2 million after 300 years. So  if it costs $1 today to prevent ecological damage worth $2 million  in the 24th century then economic theory argues that our descendants  would be better off with us putting that $1 in the bank. This would  suggest that basing our responsibility to future generations on  economics may not be the wisest course.</p>
<p>The supporter of capitalism may respond by arguing that business leaders  are as able to see long-term negative environmental effects as the rest of  us. But this is to misunderstand the nature of the objection. It is not  that business leaders <b>as individuals</b> are any less able to see what's happening to the environment. It is that if they want to keep their jobs they have to do what the system requires, which is to concentrate on what is most profitable in the short term. Thus if the president of company X has a mystical experience of oneness with nature and starts diverting profits into pollution control while the presidents of Y and Z continue with business as usual, the stockholders of company X will get a new president who is willing to focus on short-term profits like Y and Z.  As Joel Bakan stresses, managers of corporations <i>"have a legal  duty to put shareholders' interests above all others . . . Corporate  social responsibility is thus illegal -- at least when it is genuine."</i>  Ones which <i>"choose social and environmental goals over profits --  who try and act morally -- are, in fact, immoral"</i> as their role  in both the economy and economic ideology is to <i>"make much as  much money as possible for shareholders."</i> [<b>The Corporation</b>, pp. 36-7 and p. 34]</p>
<p>In general, then, if one company tries to devote resources to develop products or processes that are ecologically responsible, they will simply be undercut by other companies which are not doing so (assuming such products or processes are more expensive, as they generally are as the costs are not inflicted on other people and the planet). While some  products may survive in small niche markets which reflect the fact that many people are willing and able to pay more to protect their world, in general they will not be competitive in the market and so the ecologically damaging products will have the advantage. In other words, capitalism has  a built-in bias toward short-term gain, and this bias -- along with its inherent need for growth -- means the planet will continue its free-fall  toward ecological disaster so long as capitalism exists.</p>
<p>This suggests that attempts to address ecological problems like pollution  and depletion of resources by calling for public education are unlikely to work. While it is true that this will raise people's awareness to the  point of creating enough demand for environment-friendly technologies and  products that they will be profitable to produce, it does not solve the problem that the costs involved in doing such research now cannot be met  by a possible future demand. Moreover, the costs of such technology can initially be quite high and so the effective demand for such products may not be sufficient. For example, energy-saving light bulbs have been  around for some time but have been far more expensive that traditional ones. This means that for those on lower-incomes who would, in theory, benefit most from lower-energy bills cannot afford them. Thus their short-term income constrains undermine long-term benefits.</p>
<p>Even if the research is completed, the market itself can stop products being used. For example, the ability to produce reasonably inexpensive solar  photovoltaic power cells has existed for some time. The problem is that they  are currently very expensive and so there is a limited demand for them. This  means that no capitalist wants to risk investing in factory large enough to  take advantage of the economies of scale possible. The net effect is that  short-term considerations ensure that a viable eco-technology has been  margainalised.</p>
<p>This means that no amount of education can countermand the effects of market  forces and the short-term perspective they inflict on us all. If faced with  a tight budget and relatively expensive "ecological" products and technology,  consumers and companies may be forced to choose the cheaper, ecologically  unfriendly product to make ends meet or survive in the market. Under  capitalism, we may be free to choose, but the options are usually lousy  choices, and not the only ones potentially available in theory (this is a key problem with green consumerism -- see <a href="secE5.html">section E.5</a>).</p>
<p>The short-termism of capitalism has produced, in effect, a system which is <i>"a massive pyramid scheme that will collapse somewhere down the line when all the major players have already retired from the game.  Of course when the last of these hustlers cash in their chips, there  won't be any place left to retire to."</i> [David Watson, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 57]</p>
  <div id="book-navigation-239" class="book-navigation">

        <div class="page-links clear-block">
              <a href="secE2.html" class="page-previous" title="Go to previous page">‹ E.2 What do eco-anarchists propose instead of capitalism?</a>
                    <a href="secEcon.html" class="page-up" title="Go to parent page">up</a>
                    <a href="secE4.html" class="page-next" title="Go to next page">E.4 Can laissez-faire capitalism protect the environment? ›</a>
          </div>

  </div>
  </div>
  </body>
</html>