1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 732 733 734 735 736 737 738 739 740 741 742 743
|
\chapter{The HOL Logic}
\label{HOLlogic}
The \HOL\ system supports {\it higher order logic}. This is a version of
predicate calculus with three main extensions:
\begin{itemize}
\item Variables can range over functions and predicates
(hence `higher order').
\item The logic is {\it typed}.
\item There is no separate syntactic category of {\it formulae\/}
(terms of type \ml{bool} fulfill their role).
\end{itemize}
\section{Overview of higher order logic}
It is assumed the reader is familiar with predicate logic. The syntax
and semantics of the particular logical system supported by \HOL\ is
described in detail in \DESCRIPTION. The table below summarizes the
notation used.
\bigskip
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{|l|l|l|l|} \hline
\multicolumn{4}{|c|}{ } \\
\multicolumn{4}{|c|}{\bf Terms of the HOL Logic} \\
\multicolumn{4}{|c|}{ } \\
{\it Kind of term} & {\it \HOL\ notation} &
{\it Standard notation} &
{\it Description} \\ \hline
& & & \\
Truth & {\small\verb%T%} & $\top$ & {\it true}\\ \hline
Falsity & {\small\verb%F%} & $\bot$ & {\it false}\\ \hline
Negation & {\small\verb%~%}$t$ & $\neg t$ & {\it not}$\ t$\\ \hline
Disjunction & $t_1${\small\verb%\/%}$t_2$ & $t_1\vee t_2$ &
$t_1\ ${\it or}$\ t_2$ \\ \hline
Conjunction & $t_1${\small\verb%/\%}$t_2$ & $t_1\wedge t_2$ &
$t_1\ ${\it and}$\ t_2$ \\ \hline
Implication & $t_1${\small\verb%==>%}$t_2$ & $t_1\imp t_2$ &
$t_1\ ${\it implies}$\ t_2$ \\ \hline
Equality & $t_1${\small\verb%=%}$t_2$ & $t_1 = t_2$ &
$t_1\ ${\it equals}$\ t_2$ \\ \hline
$\forall$-quantification & {\small\verb%!%}$x${\small\verb%.%}$t$ &
$\uquant{x}t$ & {\it for\ all\ }$x: t$ \\ \hline
$\exists$-quantification & {\small\verb%?%}$x${\small\verb%.%}$t$ &
$\equant{x}\ t$ & {\it for\ some\ }$x: t$ \\ \hline
$\hilbert$-term & {\small\verb%@%}$x${\small\verb%.%}$t$ &
$\hquant{x}t$ & {\it an}$\ x\ ${\it such\ that:}$\ t$ \\ \hline
Conditional & {\small\verb%(%}$t${\small\verb%=>%}$t_1${\small\verb%|%}$t_2${\small\verb%)%} &
$(t\rightarrow t_1, t_2)$ & {\it if\ }$t${\it \ then\ }$t_1${\it\ else\ }$t_2$
\\ \hline
\end{tabular}
\end{center}\label{logic-table}
\bigskip
Terms of the \HOL\ logic are represented in \ML\ by an {\it abstract
type\/}\footnote{Abstract types appear to the user as primitive types with a
collection of operations; they are described in
\DESCRIPTION} called {\small\verb%term%}. They are normally input between
quotation marks, and anything between a pair of quotation symbols is parsed as
a logical term. For example, the expression {\small\verb%"x /\ y ==> z"%}
evaluates in \ML\ to a term representing
{\small\verb%x%}$\wedge${\small\verb%y%}$\Rightarrow${\small\verb%z%}. Terms
can be manipulated by various built-in \ML\ functions. For example, the \ML\
function \ml{dest\_imp} with \ML\ type {\small\verb%term -> term # term%}
splits an implication into a pair of terms consisting of its antecedent and
consequent, and the \ML\ function \ml{dest\_conj} of type {\small\verb%term ->
term # term%} splits a conjunction into its two conjuncts.
\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}
\begin{verbatim}
#"x /\ y ==> z";;
"x /\ y ==> z" : term
#dest_imp it;;
("x /\ y", "z") : (term # term)
#dest_conj(fst it);;
("x", "y") : (term # term)
\end{verbatim}
\end{session}
Terms of the \HOL\ logic are quite similar to \ML\ expressions, and this can at
first be confusing. Indeed, terms of the logic have types similar to those of
\ML\ expressions. For example, {\small\verb%"(1,2)"%} is an \ML\ expression
with \ML\ type {\small\verb%term%}. The \HOL\ type of this term is
{\small\verb%num#num%}. By contrast, the \ML\ expression
{\small\verb%("1","2")%} has type {\small\verb%term#term%}.
The types of \HOL\ terms form an \ML\ type called {\small\verb%type%}.
Expressions having the form {\small\verb%": %}$\cdots${\small\verb% "%}
evaluate to logical types. The built-in function {\small\verb%type_of%}
has \ML\ type {\small\verb%term->type%} and returns the logical type of a
term.
\begin{session}
\begin{verbatim}
#"(1,2)";;
"1,2" : term
#type_of it;;
":num # num" : type
#("1","2");;
("1", "2") : (term # term)
#type_of(fst it);;
":num" : type
\end{verbatim}
\end{session}
To try to minimise confusion between the logical types of \HOL\ terms and
the \ML\ types of \ML\ expressions, the former will be referred to as {\it object
language types\/} and the latter as {\it meta-language types\/}. For example,
{\small\verb%"(1,T)"%} is an \ML\ expression that has meta-language type
{\small\verb%term%} and evaluates to a term with object language type
{\small\verb%":num#bool"%}.
\begin{session}
\begin{verbatim}
#"(1,T)";;
"1,T" : term
#type_of it;;
":num # bool" : type
\end{verbatim}
\end{session}
\HOL\ terms can be input using explicit {\it quotation\/}, as above, or
they can be constructed using \ML\ constructor functions. The function
{\small\verb%mk_var%} constructs a variable from a string and a type. In
the example below, three variables of type {\small\verb%bool%} are
constructed. These are used later.
\begin{session}
\begin{verbatim}
#let x = mk_var(`x`,":bool")
#and y = mk_var(`y`,":bool")
#and z = mk_var(`z`,":bool");;
x = "x" : term
y = "y" : term
z = "z" : term
\end{verbatim}
\end{session}
The constructors {\small\verb%mk_conj%} and {\small\verb%mk_imp%} construct
conjunctions and implications respectively.
\begin{session}
\begin{verbatim}
#let t = mk_imp(mk_conj(x,y),z);;
t = "x /\ y ==> z" : term
\end{verbatim}
\end{session}
\section{Terms}
There are only four different kinds of terms:
\begin{enumerate}
\item Variables.
\item Constants.
\item Function applications: \ml{"$t_1$\ $t_2$"}.
\item $\lambda$-abstractions: {\small\verb%"\%}$x$\ml{.}$t$\ml{"}.
\end{enumerate}
Both variables and constants have a name and a type; the difference is that
constants cannot be bound by quantifiers, and their type is fixed when they are
declared (see below). The type checking algorithm uses the types of constants to
infer the types of variables in the same quotation. If there is not enough type
information a type checking error results:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"~x";;
"~x" : term
#"x";;
Indeterminate types: "x:?"
evaluation failed types indeterminate in quotation
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
In the first case, the \HOL\ type checker used the known type \ml{bool->bool}
of {\small\verb%~%} to deduce that the variable \ml{x} must have type
\ml{bool}. In the second case, it cannot deduce the type of \ml{x}. Unlike in
\ML, there must be enough information in a quotation to fully determine the
type of all subterms. The default `scope' of type information for type
checking is a single quotation, so a type in one quotation cannot affect the
type-checking of another. This scoping can be altered by using the {\it sticky
type\/} facility, which can be used to give default types to variables (see the
appropriate section of \DESCRIPTION\ for details). If there is not enough
contextually-determined type information to resolve the types of all variables
in a quotation, then it is necessary to explicitly indicate the required types
by using \ml{"$term$:$type$"} as illustrated below.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"x:num";;
"x" : term
#type_of it;;
":num" : type
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
Functions have types of the form \ml{$\sigma_1$->$\sigma_2$}, where
$\sigma_1$ and $\sigma_2$ are the types of the domain and range of the function,
respectively.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#type_of "==>";;
":bool -> (bool -> bool)" : type
#type_of "+";;
":num -> (num -> num)" : type
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent Both \ml{+} and \ml{==>} are infixes. The session below illustrates
this; it also illustrates object language versus meta-language types.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"(x+1), (t1==>t2)";;
"x + 1,(t1 ==> t2)" : term
#type_of it;;
":num # bool" : type
#"x=1","t1==>t2";;
("x = 1", "t1 ==> t2") : (term # term)
#type_of(fst it), type_of(snd it);;
(":bool", ":bool") : (type # type)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent The types of constants are declared in {\it theories}; this is
described in Section~\ref{theories}.
An application $t_1\ t_2$ is badly typed if $t_1$ is not a function:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"1 2";;
Badly typed application of: "1"
which has type: ":num"
to the argument term: "2"
which has type: ":num"
evaluation failed mk_comb in quotation
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent or if it is a function, but $t_2$ is not in its range:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"~1";;
Badly typed application of: "$~"
which has type: ":bool -> bool"
to the argument term: "1"
which has type: ":num"
evaluation failed mk_comb in quotation
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
The dollar in front of {\small\verb%~%} indicates that the constant has a special
syntactic status (in this case a non-standard precedence). Putting
{\small\verb%$%} in front of any symbol causes the parser to ignore any special
syntactic status (like being an infix) it might have.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"$==> t1 t2";;
"t1 ==> t2" : term
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
Lambda-terms, or $\lambda$-terms, denote functions. The
symbol `{\small\verb%\%}'
is used as an {\small ASCII} approximation to $\lambda$.
Thus `{\small\verb%\%}$x$\ml{.}$t$' should be read
as `$\lquant{x}t$'. For example,
{\small\verb%"\x. x+1"%} is a term that denotes the function
$n\mapsto n{+}1$.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#"\x.x+1";;
"\x. x + 1" : term
#type_of it;;
":num -> num" : type
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\section{Theories}
\label{theories}
The result of a session with the \HOL\ system is an object called a {\it
theory\/}. This object is closely related to what a logician would call a
theory, but there are some differences arising from the needs of mechanical
proof. A \HOL\ theory, like a logician's theory, contains sets of types,
constants, definitions and axioms. In addition, however, a \HOL\ theory
contains an explicit list of theorems that have been proved from the axioms
and definitions. Logicians normally do not need to distinguish theorems that
have actually been proved from those that could be proved, hence they do not
normally consider sets of proven theorems as part of a theory; rather, they
take the theorems of a theory to be the (often infinite) set of all
consequences of the axioms and definitions. Another difference between
logicians' theories and \HOL\ theories is that, for logicians, theories are
relatively static objects, but in \HOL\ they can be thought of as potentially
extendable. For example, the \HOL\ system provides tools for adding to
theories and combining theories. A typical interaction with \HOL\ consists in
combining some existing theories, making some definitions, proving some
theorems and then saving the resulting new theory.
The purpose of the \HOL\ system is to provide tools to enable well-formed
theories to be constructed. All the theorems of such theories are logical
consequences of the definitions and axioms of the theory. The \HOL\ system
ensures that only well-formed theories can be constructed by allowing
theorems to be created by {\it formal proof\/} only.
A theory is represented in the \HOL\ system as a collection of files, called
theory files. Each file has a name of the form $name$\ml{.th}, where $name$ is
a string supplied by the user.
Theory files are structured hierarchically to represent sequences of extensions of
an initial theory called \ml{HOL}.
Each theory file making up a theory records
some types, constants, axioms and
theorems, together with
pointers to other theory files called its {\it parents\/}.
This collection of reachable files is called the {\it
ancestry\/} of the theory file. Axioms, definitions
and theorems are named in the \HOL\ system by two strings: the name of the theory
file where they are stored, together with a name within that file supplied by the
user.
Specifically,
axioms, definitions and theorems
are named by a pair of strings $\langle thy,name\rangle$
where $thy$ is the name of the
theory current when the item was declared and $name$
is a specific name supplied by the user (see the functions
\ml{new\_axiom}, \ml{new\_definition} \etc\ below).
A typical piece of work with the \HOL\ system consists in a number of sessions. In
the first of these a new theory, ${\cal T}$ say, is created by extending existing
theories with a number of definitions. The concrete result of the session will be a
theory file ${\cal T}$\ml{.th} whose contents are created during the
session and whose ancestry represents the desired logical theory. In subsequent
sessions this theory is extended by proving new theorems which will be stored in
the file ${\cal T}$\ml{.th}. The logical meaning of these sessions is that a new
extension to ${\cal T}$ is created which replaces the old version. Subsequent
pieces of work can build on (\ie\ extend) the definitions and theorems of ${\cal
T}$ by making it a parent of new theories.
There are two modes of working with \HOL: {\it draft mode\/} and {\it proof
mode\/}. In draft mode, inconsistencies can be introduced by asserting
inconsistent axioms, but in proof mode only consistency preserving actions
(namely valid proof) can be done. Draft mode is analogous to `super user mode'
in Unix, in that it gives access to dangerous facilities. Everything that can
be done in proof mode can be done in draft mode, but not vice versa.
There is always a {\it current theory\/}, whose name is given by the function
\ml{current\_theory}. This function maps the value void, written
`\ml{()}' in \ML, to a string giving the name of the current theory.
Thus the \ML\ expression
\ml{current\_theory ()} evaluates to a string giving the name of the current
theory. Initially \HOL\ is in proof mode with current theory
called \ml{HOL}. So evaluating \ml{current\_theory ()} immediately after
initiating a \HOL\ session gives the value \ml{`HOL`}, as can be seen in
the session shown below:
\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
% hol
_ _ __ _ __ __
|___ |__| | | | |__| |__|
| | | |__| |__ |__| |__|
Version 2.0, built on Sep 1 1991
#current_theory();;
`HOL` : string
#
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
Executing \ml{new\_theory`$thy$`} creates a new theory called $thy$; it fails
if there already exists a file $thy$\ml{.th} in the current working
directory (or in any directory on the current \HOL\ {\it search path\/},
for a description of which, see the appropriate section of
\DESCRIPTION).
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_theory `Peano`;;
() : void
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent This starts a theory called \ml{Peano}, which is to be made into a
theory containing Peano's postulates as axioms for the natural
numbers.\footnote{An elaborate theory of numbers is built into \HOL, in which
Peano's postulates are in fact derived theorems rather than postulated as
axioms.} These postulates, stated informally, are:
\begin{list}{{\small\bf P\arabic{Peano}}}{\usecounter{Peano}
\setlength{\leftmargin}{12mm}
\setlength{\rightmargin}{7mm}
\setlength{\labelwidth}{6mm}
\setlength{\labelsep}{2mm}
\setlength{\listparindent}{0mm}
\setlength{\itemsep}{14pt plus1pt minus1pt}
\setlength{\topsep}{3mm}
\setlength{\parsep}{0mm}}
\item There is a number $0$.
\item There is a function \Suc\ called the successor function such that
if $n$ is a number then $\Suc \ n$ is a number.
\item $0$ is not the successor of any number.
\item If two numbers have the same successor then they are equal.
\item If a property holds of $0$, and if whenever it holds of a number then it
also holds of the successor of the number, then the property holds of all
numbers. This postulate is called {\it Mathematical Induction}.
\end{list}
To fomalize this in \HOL\ a new type is introduced called \ml{nat}:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_type 0 `nat`;;
() : void
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
In general \ml{new\_type}$\ n\ \ml{`\ty{op}`}$ makes \ty{op}
a new $n$-ary type operator in the current theory.
Constant types are regarded as degenerate type operators with no arguments, thus
the new type \ml{nat}
is declared to be a $0$-ary type operator. The type operator \ml{list} is
an example of a $1$-ary operator,
types built with \ml{list} are written as \ml{$\sigma\ $list}. The type
operator {\small\verb%prod%} is $2$-ary, types using it are written
as \ml{($\sigma_1$,$\sigma_2$)prod} (which can, in fact, be written as
$\sigma_1${\small\verb%#%}$\sigma_2$).
The axioms {\small\bf P1} and {\small\bf P2} can now be formalized by declaring
two new constants of type \ml{nat}
to represent $0$ and \Suc.
Evaluating \ml{new\_constant(`\con{c}`,}$\sigma$\ml{)} makes
$\con{c}$ a new constant of type $\sigma$ in the current theory.
This fails if:
\begin{myenumerate}
\item not in draft mode;
\item there already exists a constant named $\con{c}$ in the current
theory.
\end{myenumerate}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_constant(`0`, ":nat");;
evaluation failed new_constant -- 0 clashes with existing constant
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
The symbol \ml{0}
is already a constant of the built-in theory \ml{num}, and this prevents
us using it as a constant of our new theory. The symbol \ml{O} will be used
instead.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_constant(`O`,":nat");;
() : void
#new_constant(`Suc`, ":nat->nat");;
() : void
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
The \HOL\ type checker ensures that {\small\bf P1} and {\small\bf P2} hold.
{\small\bf P3} is now asserted as an axiom:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_axiom(`P3`, "!n. ~(O = Suc n)");;
|- !n. ~(O = Suc n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent This creates an axiom in the current theory (\ie\ in \ml{Peano}) called
\ml{P3}. Axiom {\small\bf P4} can be declared similarly:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_axiom(`P4`, "!m n. (Suc m = Suc n) ==> (m = n)");;
|- !m n. (Suc m = Suc n) ==> (m = n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
The final Peano axiom is Mathematical Induction:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_axiom(`P5`,"!P. P O /\ (!n. P n ==> P(Suc n)) ==> (!n. P n)");;
|- !P. P O /\ (!n. P n ==> P(Suc n)) ==> (!n. P n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
To inspect the theory, the function \ml{print\_theory} can be used:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#print_theory `Peano`;;
The Theory Peano
Parents -- HOL
Types -- ":nat"
Constants -- O ":nat" Suc ":nat -> nat"
Axioms --
P3 |- !n. ~(O = Suc n)
P4 |- !m n. (Suc m = Suc n) ==> (m = n)
P5 |- !P. P O /\ (!n. P n ==> P(Suc n)) ==> (!n. P n)
******************** Peano ********************
#\end{verbatim}\end{session}
To end the session and write out the various declarations into the theory file
\ml{Peano.th} the function \ml{close\_theory} is used.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#close_theory();;
() : void
#quit();;
% ls Peano.th
Peano.th
%
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent The function \ml{quit} exits from the \HOL\ system.
The preceding session set up a theory called \ml{Peano}. It is usual
to include in `Peano arithmetic' axioms defining addition and multiplication.
To do this a new session can be started and the theory extended.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
% hol
_ _ __ _ __ __
|___ |__| | | | |__| |__|
| | | |__| |__ |__| |__|
Version 2.0 (Sun3/Franz), built on Sep 1 1991
#extend_theory `Peano`;;
Theory Peano loaded
() : void
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent The two new axioms can now be added, but first constants \ml{add} and
\ml{mult} must be declared to represent addition and multiplication (the
symbols \ml{+} and \ml{*} are already in use). These can be declared as
infixes using \ml{new\_infix} instead of \ml{new\_constant}.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_infix(`add`,":nat->nat->nat");;
() : void
#new_infix(`mult`,":nat->(nat->nat)");;
() : void
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent Constants declared with \ml{new\_infix}
must have a type of the form
\ml{$\sigma$->($\sigma$->$\sigma$)}.
Axioms defining \ml{add} and \ml{mult} can now be defined.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_axiom
# (`add_def`,
# "(!n. O add n = n) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) add n = Suc(m add n))");;
|- (!n. O add n = n) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) add n = Suc(m add n))
#new_axiom
# (`mult_def`,
# "(!n. O mult n = O) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) mult n = (m mult n) add n)");;
|- (!n. O mult n = O) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) mult n = (m mult n) add n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent The theory \ml{Peano} has now been extended to contain the new
definitions.
This example shows how a theory is set up. How to prove consequences of axioms and
definitions is described later. The \HOL\ system contains a built-in
theory of numbers called \ml{num} which contains Peano's postulates and a
(descendent) theory \ml{arithmetic} containing the definitions of addition
(\ml{+}) and multiplication (\ml{*}) and other things.
In fact, Peano's
postulates are theorems not axioms in the theory \ml{num}. The primitive constants
\ml{0} and \ml{SUC} (corresponding to \ml{O} and \ml{Suc} in \ml{Peano}) are
{\it defined\/} in terms of purely logical notions.
In \HOL, {\it definitions\/} are a special kind of axiom that are
guaranteed to be consistent. The commonest (but not only) form of a definition is:
\[f\ x_1\ \ldots\ x_n = t\]
\noindent where $f$ is declared to be a new constant satisfying this
equation (and $t$ is a term whose free variables are included in the set
$\{x_1,\ldots,x_n\}$). Such definitions cannot be recursive because, for
example:
\[ f\ x = (f\ x)+1 \]
\noindent would imply $0=1$ (subtract $f\ x$ from both sides)
and is therefore inconsistent. An example of a definition is:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#new_definition(`Double_def`, "Double x = x add x");;
|- !x. Double x = x add x
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent This definition both declares \ml{Double} as a new constant of the
appropriate type and asserts the defining equation as a definitional axiom.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#print_theory `Peano`;;
The Theory Peano
Parents -- HOL
Types -- ":nat"
Constants --
add ":nat -> (nat -> nat)" mult ":nat -> (nat -> nat)"
O ":nat" Suc ":nat -> nat" Double ":nat -> nat"
Infixes --
add ":nat -> (nat -> nat)" mult ":nat -> (nat -> nat)"
Axioms --
P3 |- !n. ~(O = Suc n)
P4 |- !m n. (Suc m = Suc n) ==> (m = n)
P5 |- !P. P O /\ (!n. P n ==> P(Suc n)) ==> (!n. P n)
add_def |- (!n. O add n = n) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) add n = Suc(m add n))
mult_def
|- (!n. O mult n = O) /\ (!m n. (Suc m) mult n = (m mult n) add n)
Definitions -- Double_def |- !x. Double x = x add x
******************** Peano ********************
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
The use of axioms, as illustrated here, carries considerable danger in general
because it is very easy to assert inconsistent axioms. It is thus safer to use
only definitions. At first sight this might appear impossible, but in fact all
of ordinary mathematics can be developed from logic by definition alone.
Showing this was the achievement of Russell and Whitehead in their treatise
{\sl Principia Mathematica} \cite{Principia}. A theory containing only
definitions is called a {\it definitional theory\/}. Many useful definitional
theories are built into the \HOL\ system, or available as libraries. Examples
include theories of numbers (both natural numbers and integers), sets, bags,
finite trees, group theory, properties of fixed points and more. Libraries are
constantly being added to \HOL\ and users are encouraged to contribute new
theories to the library when they develop them.
\newpage % PBHACK
The theory of numbers built into \HOL\ is a definitional theory that defines
numbers logically. Peano's postulates are proved from the definitions of
the type \ml{num} and the constants \ml{0} and \ml{SUC}.
It follows from Peano's postulates that certain kinds of recursion equations are
equivalent to non-recursive definitions. There is a built-in theory called
\ml{prim\_rec} (for `primitive recursion') that supports this,
together with tools for automatically transforming recursion equations into
definitions. This is illustrated later but, for example, here are the built-in
definitions of \ml{+} and \ml{*}:
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#ADD;;
Definition ADD autoloaded from theory `arithmetic`.
ADD = |- (!n. 0 + n = n) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) + n = SUC(m + n))
|- (!n. 0 + n = n) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) + n = SUC(m + n))
#MULT;;
Definition MULT autoloaded from theory `arithmetic`.
MULT = |- (!n. 0 * n = 0) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) * n = (m * n) + n)
|- (!n. 0 * n = 0) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) * n = (m * n) + n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent This also illustrates how certain built-in definitions (and theorems)
are `autoloaded' from the theories where they are defined (\ml{arithmetic} in this
case).
\newpage % PBHACK
The theory \ml{arithmetic} contains too many pre-proved theorems to show in
full, but here are the constants, definitions, and the first two (out of
113) theorems.
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#print_theory `arithmetic`;;
The Theory arithmetic
Parents -- BASIC-HOL prim_rec
Constants --
+ ":num -> (num -> num)" - ":num -> (num -> num)"
* ":num -> (num -> num)" EXP ":num -> (num -> num)"
> ":num -> (num -> bool)" <= ":num -> (num -> bool)"
>= ":num -> (num -> bool)" MOD ":num -> (num -> num)"
DIV ":num -> (num -> num)"
Infixes --
+ ":num -> (num -> num)" - ":num -> (num -> num)"
* ":num -> (num -> num)" EXP ":num -> (num -> num)"
> ":num -> (num -> bool)" <= ":num -> (num -> bool)"
>= ":num -> (num -> bool)" MOD ":num -> (num -> num)"
DIV ":num -> (num -> num)"
Definitions --
ADD |- (!n. 0 + n = n) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) + n = SUC(m + n))
SUB
|- (!m. 0 - m = 0) /\
(!m n. (SUC m) - n = (m < n => 0 | SUC(m - n)))
MULT |- (!n. 0 * n = 0) /\ (!m n. (SUC m) * n = (m * n) + n)
EXP |- (!m. m EXP 0 = 1) /\ (!m n. m EXP (SUC n) = m * (m EXP n))
GREATER |- !m n. m > n = n < m
LESS_OR_EQ |- !m n. m <= n = m < n \/ (m = n)
GREATER_OR_EQ |- !m n. m >= n = m > n \/ (m = n)
DIVISION
|- !n.
0 < n ==>
(!k. (k = ((k DIV n) * n) + (k MOD n)) /\ (k MOD n) < n)
Theorems --
SUC_NOT |- !n. ~(0 = SUC n)
ADD_0 |- !m. m + 0 = m
.
.
.
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\noindent Note that \ml{DIV} is defined by a constant specification. See
\DESCRIPTION\ for further explanation.
|