File: tactics.tex

package info (click to toggle)
hol88 2.02.19940316dfsg-8
  • links: PTS
  • area: main
  • in suites: forky, sid
  • size: 65,960 kB
  • sloc: ml: 199,939; ansic: 9,666; sh: 6,913; makefile: 6,032; lisp: 2,747; yacc: 894; sed: 201; cpp: 87; awk: 5
file content (2454 lines) | stat: -rw-r--r-- 86,789 bytes parent folder | download | duplicates (11)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970
1971
1972
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
1982
1983
1984
1985
1986
1987
1988
1989
1990
1991
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
2017
2018
2019
2020
2021
2022
2023
2024
2025
2026
2027
2028
2029
2030
2031
2032
2033
2034
2035
2036
2037
2038
2039
2040
2041
2042
2043
2044
2045
2046
2047
2048
2049
2050
2051
2052
2053
2054
2055
2056
2057
2058
2059
2060
2061
2062
2063
2064
2065
2066
2067
2068
2069
2070
2071
2072
2073
2074
2075
2076
2077
2078
2079
2080
2081
2082
2083
2084
2085
2086
2087
2088
2089
2090
2091
2092
2093
2094
2095
2096
2097
2098
2099
2100
2101
2102
2103
2104
2105
2106
2107
2108
2109
2110
2111
2112
2113
2114
2115
2116
2117
2118
2119
2120
2121
2122
2123
2124
2125
2126
2127
2128
2129
2130
2131
2132
2133
2134
2135
2136
2137
2138
2139
2140
2141
2142
2143
2144
2145
2146
2147
2148
2149
2150
2151
2152
2153
2154
2155
2156
2157
2158
2159
2160
2161
2162
2163
2164
2165
2166
2167
2168
2169
2170
2171
2172
2173
2174
2175
2176
2177
2178
2179
2180
2181
2182
2183
2184
2185
2186
2187
2188
2189
2190
2191
2192
2193
2194
2195
2196
2197
2198
2199
2200
2201
2202
2203
2204
2205
2206
2207
2208
2209
2210
2211
2212
2213
2214
2215
2216
2217
2218
2219
2220
2221
2222
2223
2224
2225
2226
2227
2228
2229
2230
2231
2232
2233
2234
2235
2236
2237
2238
2239
2240
2241
2242
2243
2244
2245
2246
2247
2248
2249
2250
2251
2252
2253
2254
2255
2256
2257
2258
2259
2260
2261
2262
2263
2264
2265
2266
2267
2268
2269
2270
2271
2272
2273
2274
2275
2276
2277
2278
2279
2280
2281
2282
2283
2284
2285
2286
2287
2288
2289
2290
2291
2292
2293
2294
2295
2296
2297
2298
2299
2300
2301
2302
2303
2304
2305
2306
2307
2308
2309
2310
2311
2312
2313
2314
2315
2316
2317
2318
2319
2320
2321
2322
2323
2324
2325
2326
2327
2328
2329
2330
2331
2332
2333
2334
2335
2336
2337
2338
2339
2340
2341
2342
2343
2344
2345
2346
2347
2348
2349
2350
2351
2352
2353
2354
2355
2356
2357
2358
2359
2360
2361
2362
2363
2364
2365
2366
2367
2368
2369
2370
2371
2372
2373
2374
2375
2376
2377
2378
2379
2380
2381
2382
2383
2384
2385
2386
2387
2388
2389
2390
2391
2392
2393
2394
2395
2396
2397
2398
2399
2400
2401
2402
2403
2404
2405
2406
2407
2408
2409
2410
2411
2412
2413
2414
2415
2416
2417
2418
2419
2420
2421
2422
2423
2424
2425
2426
2427
2428
2429
2430
2431
2432
2433
2434
2435
2436
2437
2438
2439
2440
2441
2442
2443
2444
2445
2446
2447
2448
2449
2450
2451
2452
2453
2454
\chapter{Goal Directed Proof: Tactics and Tacticals}

\label{tactics-and-tacticals}

\index{tactics!purpose of|(}
There are three primary devices that together make theorem proving practical
in \HOL. All three originate with Milner
\index{Milner, R.}\index{LCF@\LCF!Edinburgh} for Edinburgh \LCF.
The first is the theory as
a record of (among other things) facts already proved
and thence available as lemmas
\index{lemmas}
without having to be re-proved.  The second,
the subject of Chapter~\ref{derived-rules}, is the
derived rule of inference as a meta-language procedure that implements a
broad pattern of inference, but that also, at each application,
generates every primitive step of the proof. The third device is
the tactic as a means of organizing the construction of proofs;
and the use of tacticals for composing tactics.

Even with recourse to derived inference rules,
it is still surprisingly awkward to work forward,
\index{forward proof!compared to goal directed} to find a chain of
theorems that culminates in a desired theorem.  This is in part because
chains have no structure, while `proof efforts' do.  For instance, if
within one sequence, two chains of steps
are to be combined in the end by conjunction, then
one chain must follow or be interspersed with
the other in the overall sequence.  It can also be difficult to direct
the proof toward its object when starting from
only hypotheses (if any), lemmas (if any),
axioms, and theorems following from no hypotheses
(\eg\ by \ml{ASSUME} or \ml{REFL}). Likewise, it can be equally difficult
to reconstruct
\index{tactics!as documentation of proofs}
the plan of the proof effort after the fact, from the
linear sequence of theorems; the sequence is unhelpful as documentation.

The idea of goal directed proof\index{goal directed proof search!reason for} is a simple one, well known in
artificial intelligence: to organize the search\index{proof construction!as tree search} as a tree, and to reverse
the process and {\it begin\/} with the objective. The goal is then
decomposed, successively if necessary,
into what one hopes are more tractable subgoals, each decomposition
accompanied by a
plan for translating the solution of subgoals into a solution of the goal.
The choice of decomposition is an explicit way of expressing a proof
`strategy'.
\index{strategies, for proof} 

Thus, for example, instead of
the linear sequencing of two branches of the proof of the conjunction,
each branch starting from scratch, the proof task is organized
as a tree search, starting with a conjunctive goal
and decomposing it into the two conjunct subgoals (undertaken in optional
order), with the intention of conjoining the two solutions when and if found.
The proof itself, as a sequence of steps, is the same however it is found;
the difference is in the search, and in the preservation, if required, of
the structured proof plan.

The representation of this idea in \LCF\ was Milner's inspiration;
the idea is similarly central to theorem proving in \HOL.
Although subgoaling theorem provers had already been built at the time,
Milner's particular contribution was in formalizing the method for
translating subgoals solutions to solutions of goals.



%The tactics and tacticals in the \HOL\ system are derived from those in the
%Cambridge \LCF\ system \cite{new-LCF-man} (which evolved 
%from the ones
%in Edinburgh \LCF\ \cite{Edinburgh-LCF}).

\section{Tactics, goals and justifications}
\label{tactics}

\index{goal directed proof search!concepts of|(}
A {\it tactic\/}\index{proof steps, as ML function applications@proof steps, as \ML\ function applications} is an \ML\ function that when applied to a {\it goal\/} 
\index{goals, in HOL system@goals, in \HOL\ system}
reduces it to (i) a list\footnote{The ordering is necessary for selecting
a tree search strategy.} of 
(sub)goals, along with (ii) a {\it justification\/}
\index{justifications, in goal-directed proof search}
 function mapping
a list of theorems to a theorem.
The idea is that the function justifies the decomposition of the goal.
%that respectively {\it achieve\/} the (sub)goals
%to a theorem that achieves the goal.  
A goal is an \ML\ value whose type is isomorphic
to, but distinct from, the \ML\ abstract type \ml{thm} of theorems.
That is, a goal is
a list of terms ({\it assumptions\/})
\index{assumption list, of goal} paired with a term.
\index{term component, of goal}
These two components correspond, respectively, to the list of hypotheses
and the conclusion of a theorem. The list of assumptions is a working
record of facts that may be used in decomposing the goal.

The relation of theorems
to goals is achievement:
\index{achievement, of goals} a theorem achieves a goal if the conclusion
of the theorem is equal to the term part of the goal
(up to $\alpha$-conversion), and if each hypothesis of the theorem
is equal (up to $\alpha$-conversion, again) to some assumption of the
goal. This definition assures that the theorem purporting to satisfy a goal
does not depend on assumptions beyond the
working assumptions of the goal.

A justification is (rather confusingly) called
a {\it proof\/}
\index{proofs, in HOL logic@proofs, in \HOL\ logic!as ML function applications@as \ML\ function applications}\index{proof functions (same as justifications, validations)}
in \HOL\, following the \LCF\ usage; it is, as mentioned,
an \ML\ function
from a theorem list to a theorem.  The \ML\ `proof' function 
corresponds to a proof
\index{proofs, in HOL logic@proofs, in \HOL\ logic!as generated by tactics} in the
logical sense (of a sequence of theorems depending on inference\index{inferences, in HOL logic@inferences, in \HOL\ logic!in goal-directed proof search} rules)
only in that it must
evaluate the \ML\ function corresponding
to each inference rule on which the sequence depends 
in order to compute its \ml{thm}-valued result. (`Justification', or
`validation',
\index{validations} as is sometimes used, are less confusing terms for
the \ML\ function in question.)
The proof function, or justification, returned by a tactic is intended to map the
list of theorems respectively achieving the subgoals to the
theorem achieving the original goal; it justifies the decomposition
into subgoals.

A tactic is said to {\it solve\/}
\index{solving, of goals} a goal if it reduces the goal to the
empty set of subgoals. 
This depends, obviously, on there being at least one
tactic that maps a goal to the empty subgoal list.  The simplest
tactic that does this is one that can recognize when a goal is
achieved by an axiom or an existing theorem; in \HOL, the function
\ml{ACCEPT\_TAC}\index{ACCEPT_TAC@\ml{ACCEPT\_TAC}}
 does this. \ml{ACCEPT\_TAC} takes a theorem $th$
and produces a tactic that maps a value
of type \ml{thm} to the empty list of subgoals. It justifies this
`decomposition' by a proof function that maps the empty list of theorems
to the theorem $th$. The use of this technical device, or other
such tactics, ends the decomposition of subgoals, and allows the proof
to be built up.\index{tactics!purpose of|)}

Unlike theorems, goals need not be defined as an abstract type;
they are transparent and can be constructed freely. Thus, an \ML\
type abbreviation (see Section~\ref{MLtypeabbrev}) is introduced 
for goals.\footnote{However,
if goals were an abstract type, the print
abbreviation could be avoided where not intended.}. 
The operations on goals are therefore just the ordinary
pair selectors and constructor (see Section~\ref{avra_predeclared}).
Likewise, type abbreviations are introduced for justifications (proofs)
and tactics. Conceptually, the following abbreviations are made in \HOL:

\begin{hol}
\index{goal@\ml{goal}}
\index{tactic@\ml{tactic}}
\index{proof@\ml{proof}}
\index{tactics!ML type of@\ML\ type of}
\begin{verbatim}
   goal       = term list # term
   tactic     = goal -> goal list # proof
   proof      = thm list -> thm
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\index{subgoals@\ml{subgoals}}
In fact, the type {\small\verb%goal list # proof%} is abbreviated in \ML\
to \ml{subgoals}, and the abbreviation of \ml{tactic} made
indirectly through it.
Thus, if $T$ is a tactic  and $g$ 
is a goal, then
applying $T$ to $g$ (\ie\ evaluating the \ML\ 
expression $T\ g$) results in
an \ML\ value of type \ml{subgoals}, \ie\ a pair whose 
first component is a list of goals and whose second component has
\ML\ type {\small\verb%proof%}. (The word `tactic' is occasionally
used loosely to mean a tactic-valued function.)


%It  will simplify the description of tactics if various \ML\ 
%{\it type abbreviations\/}
%are used in the sections 
%that follow.\footnote{Do not confuse ML type abbreviations (see
%Section~\ref{MLtypeabbrev}) with HOL logic type abbreviations (see
%Section~\ref{typeabbrev}).}  An \ML\  type abbreviation is just a 
%name given to an
%\ML\ type; a type and its abbreviation can be used 
%interchangeably. By default, the
%system prints types using any \ML\ abbreviations that are in force, 
%but this can be
%changed by setting the flag \ml{print\_lettypes} to \ml{false}.  A type
%abbreviation is introduced by executing a declaration of the form 

%\[ \ml{lettype } name \ml{ = } type \]

%\noindent For example:

%\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
%   lettype goal = term list # term
%\end{verbatim}\end{hol}


It does not follow, of course, from the type \ml{tactic} that a
particular tactic is well-behaved. For example,
suppose that
$T\ g${\small\verb% = ([%}$g_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots
${\small\verb%;%}$g_n${\small\verb%],%}$p${\small\verb%)%}, and that
the subgoals $g_1$ , $\dots$, $g_n$ have been solved.
That means that some
theorems $th_1$ , $\dots$, $th_n$ have been proved
such that each $th_i$ ($1\leq i\leq n$) achieves the goal $g_i$. 
The justification $p$
is intended to be a
function that when applied to the list
{\small\verb%[%}$th_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;%}$th_n${\small\verb%]%}, 
succeeds in returning a theorem, $th$, 
achieving the original goal $g$; but, of course, it might sometimes
not succeed. If $p$ 
succeeds for every list of achieving theorems, then the tactic $T$ is
said to be {\it valid\/}\index{validity, of tactics|(}. This does not guarantee, however, that
the subgoals are solvable in the first place. If, in addition
to being valid, a tactic always produces solvable subgoals from a
solvable goal, it is called {\it strongly valid\/}.
\index{strong validity, of tactics}

Tactics can be perfectly useful without being 
strongly valid, or without
even being valid;
in fact, some of the most basic theorem proving strategies, expressed
as tactics, are invalid or not strongly valid.\footnote{The subgoal
package, discussed later in the chapter, prevents the use of
invalid tactics when they are liable to result in unexpected
theorem results, but the \HOL\ system used directly allows 
it.} An invalid tactic
cannot result in the proof of false theorems;
\index{consistency, of HOL logic@consistency, of \HOL\ logic|(}
\index{security, in goal directed proof|(}
theorems in \HOL\
are always the result of performing a proof in the basic logic,
whether the proof is found by goal directed search
or forward search.\footnote{`Invalid' is perhaps a misleading term, since
there is nothing logically amiss in the use of invalid tactics
or the theorems produced thereby; but the term has stuck over time.} However, an
invalid tactic may produce an unintended theorem---one that does not
achieve the original goal. The typical case is when a theorem
purporting to achieve a goal
actually depends on hypotheses that extend beyond the assumptions of
the goal.  The inconvenience to the \HOL\ user in this case
is that the problem may be not immediately 
obvious; the default print format of theorems has
hypotheses abbreviated as dots. Invalidity may also be the result of the
failure
\index{failure, of tactics|(}
 of the proof function, in the \ML\ sense of failure, when
applied to a list of theorems (if, for example, the function were
defined incorrectly); but again, no false theorems can result.
Likewise, a tactic that is not strongly valid cannot result in a false
theorem; the worst outcome of applying such a tactic is the production
of unsolvable subgoals\index{consistency, of HOL logic@consistency, of \HOL\ logic|)}\index{security, in goal directed proof|)}\index{validity, of tactics|)}.

%If $T$ were invalid and were used
%to reduce goal $g$ to subgoals $g_1$ , $\dots$, $g_n$,
%then 
%theorems $th_1$ , $\dots$, $th_n$ might be proved to
%achieve $g_1$ , $\dots$, $g_n$, but this turns out to be a blind alley
%because $p${\small\verb%[%}$th_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;%}$th_n${\small\verb%]%} 
%doesn't achieve $g$ (\ie\ it fails, 
%or else it achieves some other goal).

Tactics are specified using the following notation:
\index{notation!for specification of tactics}

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$goal$ \\ \hline \hline
$goal_1\ \ \ goal_2 \ \ \ \ldots\ \ \ goal_n$ \\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent For example, the 
tactic for decomposing conjunctions into
two  conjunct subgoals is called {\small\verb%CONJ_TAC%}.
\index{CONJ_TAC@\ml{CONJ\_TAC}}  It is described by:

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$ t_1${\small\verb% /\ %}$t_2$ \\ \hline \hline
$t_1\ \ \ \ \ \ \ t_2$ \\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent This indicates
that {\small\verb%CONJ_TAC%} reduces a goal of the form 
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t_1${\small\verb%/\%}$t_2${\small\verb%)%} 
to subgoals
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t_1${\small\verb%)%} and {\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t_2${\small\verb%)%}.
The fact that the assumptions of the original goal
are propagated unchanged to the two subgoals is indicated by the absence
of assumptions in the notation. The notation gives no indication of the
proof function.

Another example is {\small\verb%INDUCT_TAC%}\index{INDUCT_TAC@\ml{INDUCT\_TAC}}\index{induction tactics},
the tactic for performing mathematical induction
on the natural numbers:

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
{\small\verb%!%}$n${\small\verb%.%}$t[n]$ \\ \hline \hline
$t[${\small\verb%0%}$]$ {\small\verb%     %} $\{t[n]\}\ t[${\small\verb%SUC %}$n]$
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

{\small\verb%INDUCT_TAC%} reduces a goal of the form
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,!%}$n${\small\verb%.%}$t[n]${\small\verb%)%} to a basis subgoal
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t[${\small\verb%0%}$]${\small\verb%)%} 
and an induction step subgoal 
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma\cup\{${\small\verb%%}$t[n]${\small\verb%%}$\}${\small\verb%,%}$t[${\small\verb%SUC %}$n]${\small\verb%)%}.
The induction assumption
is indicated in the tactic notation with set brackets.

Tactics fail
\index{failure, of tactics|)}
(in the \ML\ sense) if they are applied to 
inappropriate
goals. For example, {\small\verb%CONJ_TAC%} will fail if it is applied to a goal whose
conclusion is not a conjunction. Some tactics never fail; for example
{\small\verb%ALL_TAC%}\index{ALL_TAC@\ml{ALL\_TAC}}

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$t$ \\ \hline \hline
$t$
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent is the identity tactic;
\index{identity tactic} it reduces a goal 
{\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t${\small\verb%)%} 
to the single
subgoal {\small\verb%(%}$\Gamma${\small\verb%,%}$t${\small\verb%)%}---\ie\ 
it has no effect. {\small\verb%ALL_TAC%} is useful for writing
compound tactics, as discussed later (see Section~\ref{tacticals}).

In just the way that the derived rule \ml{REWRITE\_RULE}\index{REWRITE_TAC@\ml{REWRITE\_TAC}|(}
 is central
to forward proof (Section~\ref{avra_rewrite}), the corresponding
function \ml{REWRITE\_TAC}
\index{rewriting!main tactic for|(}
\index{rewriting!importance of, in goal directed proof|(}
is central to goal
directed proof.  Given a goal and a list of equational theorems, 
\ml{REWRITE\_TAC} transforms the term component of the goal by
applying the equations as left-to-right rewrites, recursively and
to all depths, until no more changes can be made.  Unless not
required, the function includes as rewrites the same
standard set of pre-proved tautologies
\index{tautologies, in rewriting tactic}
that \ml{REWRITE\_RULE} uses.
By use of the tautologies, some subgoals can be solved
internally by rewriting, and in that case, an empty list of subgoals
is returned. The transformation of the goal is justified in each case by the
appropriate chain of inferences.
Rewriting often does a large share of the work in goal directed proof searches.\index{goal directed proof search!concepts of|)}\index{REWRITE_TAC@\ml{REWRITE\_TAC}|)}
\index{rewriting!importance of, in goal directed proof|)}
\index{rewriting!main tactic for|)}

A simple example from list theory (Section~\ref{avra_list}) 
illustrates the use of tactics.
A conjunctive goal is declared, and \ml{CONJ\_TAC} applied to it:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#let g = ([]:term list),"(HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])";;
g = ([], "(HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])") : goal

#let gl1,p1 = CONJ_TAC g;;
gl1 = [([], "HD[1;2;3] = 1"); ([], "TL[1;2;3] = [2;3]")] : goal list
p1 = - : proof
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The subgoals are each rewritten, using the definitions of
\ml{"HD"} and \ml{"TL"}:

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#HD;;
Definition HD autoloaded from theory `list`.
HD = |- !h t. HD(CONS h t) = h

|- !h t. HD(CONS h t) = h

#TL;;
Definition TL autoloaded from theory `list`.
TL = |- !h t. TL(CONS h t) = t

|- !h t. TL(CONS h t) = t

#let gl1_1,p1_1 = REWRITE_TAC[HD;TL](hd gl1);;
gl1_1 = [] : goal list
p1_1 = - : proof

#let gl1_2,p1_2 = REWRITE_TAC[HD;TL](hd(tl gl1));;
gl1_2 = [] : goal list
p1_2 = - : proof
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent Both of the two subgoals are now solved, so 
the decomposition is complete and
the proof can be built up in stages.  First the theorems achieving the
subgoals are proved, then from those, the theorem achieving the original goal:
\vfill
\newpage
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#let th1 = p1_1[];;
th1 = |- HD[1;2;3] = 1

#let th2 = p1_2[];;
th2 = |- TL[1;2;3] = [2;3]

#p1[th1;th2];;
|- (HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent Although only the theorems achieving the subgoals are `seen' here,
the proof functions of the three tactic applications together perform
the entire chain\index{goal directed proof search!generation of proofs by}\index{proofs, in HOL logic@proofs, in \HOL\ logic!as generated by tactics}
 of inferences leading to the theorem achieving the goal.
The same proof could be constructed by forward search, starting from
the definitions of \ml{"HD"} and \ml{"TL"}, but not nearly as easily.

The \HOL\ system provides a collection of pre-defined tactics (and
\ml{tactic}-valued functions) that includes
\ml{CONJ\_TAC}, \ml{INDUCT\_TAC}, \ml{ALL\_TAC}  and
\ml{REWRITE\_TAC}. The pre-defined tactics
are adequate for many applications.  In addition, there are two means of
defining new tactics.
\index{tactics!definition of new}
Since a tactic\index{proof steps, as ML function applications@proof steps, as \ML\ function applications} is an \ML\ function, the user
can define a new tactic directly in \ML.  Definitions of this sort
use \ML\ functions to construct the term part of the subgoals from
the term part of the original goal (if any transformation is required); 
and they specify the justification,
which expects a list of theorems achieving the subgoals and
returns the theorem achieving (one hopes) the goal.
The proof of the theorem is encoded in the definition of the justification
 function;
that is, the means for deriving the desired theorem from the theorems
given. This typically involves references to axioms and
primitive and defined inference rules,
and is usually the more difficult part of the project.

A simple example of a tactic written in \ML\index{proofs, in HOL logic@proofs, in \HOL\ logic!as ML function applications@as \ML\ function applications}\ is afforded by \ml{CONJ\_TAC},
whose definition in \HOL\ is as follows:

\begin{hol}
\index{CONJ_TAC@\ml{CONJ\_TAC}!ML implementation of@\ML\ implementation of}
\begin{verbatim}
   let CONJ_TAC : tactic (asl,w) =
   (let l,r = dest_conj w in
              [(asl,l);(asl,r)],(\[th1;th2].CONJ th1 th2)
   ) ? failwith `CONJ_TAC`;;
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent This shows how the subgoals are constructed, and how the
proof function is specified in terms of the derived rule \ml{CONJ}
(Section~\ref{avra_conj}).

The second method is to compose
\index{tactics!indirect implementation of}
\index{tactics!compound}
\index{proof construction}
existing tactics by the use 
of \ML\ functions called {\it tacticals\/}.
\index{tacticals}
The tacticals provided in \HOL\ are listed in Section~\ref{tacticals}.
For example, two existing tactics can be sequenced
\index{sequencing!of tactics}
\index{tactics!sequencing of}
 by use of the
tactical \ml{THEN}:\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}}
if $T_1$ and
$T_2$ are  tactics,  then the  \ML\ expression  $T_1${\small\verb% THEN %}$T_2$
evaluates to a  tactic that first applies  $T_1$ to  a goal  and then applies
$T_2$ to each subgoal produced by $T_1$.   The  tactical {\small\verb%THEN%} is
an infixed \ML\ function. Complex and powerful tactics can be
constructed in this way; and new tacticals can also be defined, although
this is unusual.

The example from earlier
is continued, to illustrate the use of the tactical \ml{THEN}:

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#let gl2,p2 = (CONJ_TAC THEN REWRITE_TAC[HD;TL])g;;
gl2 = [] : goal list
p2 = - : proof

#p2[];;
|- (HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The single tactic \ml{CONJ\_TAC THEN REWRITE\_TAC[HD;TL]}
solves the goal in one single application. The chain of inference computed,
however, is exactly the same as in the interactive proof; only the search is
different.

In general, the second method is both easier and more reliable.  It is
easier because it does not involve writing \ML\ procedures (usually
rather complicated procedures); and more reliable because
the composed tactics are valid
\index{validity, of tactics} when the constituent tactics are valid,
as a consequence of the way the tacticals are defined. Tactics written
directly in \ML\ may fail\index{failure, of tactics!debugging}\index{failure, of tactics|(}\index{debugging, of tactics}\index{tactics!debugging of}
 in a variety of ways, and although, as usual,
they cannot cause false theorems to appear, the failures can be difficult
to understand and trace.\footnote{A possible extension to \HOL\
would be a `debugging environment' for this class of tactic.} On the other
hand, there are some proof strategies that cannot be implemented as
compositions of existing tactics, and these have to be implemented
directly in \ML.  Certain sorts of inductions are an example of this;
as well as tactics to support some personal styles of proof.



\subsection{Details of proving theorems}
\label{using-tactics}

When a theorem is proved that the user wishes to preserve for future use,
it can be stored in the current theory 
by using the function \ml{save\_thm} (see Section~\ref{theoryprims}).

To simplify the use of tactics there are three standard functions

\index{TAC_PROOF@\ml{TAC\_PROOF}|pin}
\index{prove_thm@\ml{prove\_thm}|pin}
\index{PROVE@\ml{PROVE}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   TAC_PROOF : (goal # tactic) -> thm
   prove_thm : (string # term # tactic) -> thm
   PROVE     : (term # tactic) -> thm
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent \ml{TAC\_PROOF} takes a goal and a tactic, and applies the
tactic to the goal; the goal can have assumptions.
Executing 
{\small\verb%prove_thm(`foo`,%}$t${\small\verb%,%}$T${\small\verb%)%} 
proves the goal {\small\verb%([],%}$t${\small\verb%)%} (\ie\ the 
goal with no assumptions and conclusion $t$) 
using tactic
$T$ and saves the resulting theorem with 
name {\small\verb%foo%} on the current
theory.
Executing {\small\verb%PROVE(%}$t${\small\verb%,%}$T${\small\verb%)%} 
proves the goal {\small\verb%([],%}$t${\small\verb%)%}
using 
$T$ and returns the result without saving it. In all
cases the evaluation fails
if $T$ does not solve the goal  {\small\verb%([],%}$t${\small\verb%)%}.

In short, \HOL\ provides a very general framework in which proof
strategies can be designed, implemented, applied and tested.  Tactics
range from the very simple to the very advanced; in theory, a
conventional automatic theorem prover could be expressed as a tactic or group
of tactics.  In contrast, some users never have need to go beyond the
built in tactics of the system.  The vital support that \HOL\ provides
in all cases is the assurance that only theorems of the deductive system
can be represented as theorems of the \HOL\ system---security is
always preserved.


\section{The subgoal package}

It was mentioned earlier that goal directed proof is a way of
organizing the construction of a proof as a tree search.  For any
tactic and goal, the tactic implicitly determines a tree\index{subgoal tree!in proof construction}\index{tree of subgoals, in proof construction} of subgoals
for that goal: each node is a subgoal, and each edge is a tactic.
Associated with each node in a successful proof effort is also an
achieving theorem---the theorem that achieves that subgoal.
That is, the tree is traversed in two phases: from the root (the original
goal) to the final layer of subgoals; and from the theorems achieving
the final subgoals back to the theorem achieving the goal at the root.
The first phase is the decomposition phase,
\index{goal directed proof search!decomposition phase of}
\index{decomposition phase, of proof search}
 in which goals are reduced
to subgoals (and eventually to trivial subgoals). The second phase
is the computation
\index{goal directed proof search!composition phase of}
\index{computation phase, of proof search}
of the proof, through each primitive step,
culminating in the desired theorem.
The tree,
however, is not explicitly represented in the \HOL\ system, so each
proof effort requires some amount of book-keeping: application of tactics 
to goals, naming of subgoals and proof functions,
application of the appropriate
proof functions to theorem lists, naming of theorems, and so on.

When conducting a proof that involves many subgoals and tactics, 
it is difficult
to keep track of this book-keeping.
While it is actually feasible for the user to take responsibility,
even in large proofs, it is tedious and error-prone.
Therefore \HOL\ provides a package
traversing the tree of subgoals once through, stacking the subgoals
and proof functions, and applying the proof functions 
automatically, when appropriate
to do so.
This package was originally implemented for Cambridge \LCF\ by
\index{LCF@\LCF!Cambridge} Paulson.\index{Paulson, L.}

The subgoal package\index{inferences, in HOL logic@inferences, in \HOL\ logic!in goal-directed proof search} implements a simple framework for interactive proof,
and this is adequate for most users in most applications. 
The tree is traversed depth first.  The current goal can be expanded
into subgoals and a proof function by supplying it with a tactic; 
the subgoals are pushed onto a goal
stack
\index{stacks, in subgoal package} and the justifications onto a proof stack.
Subgoals  at the same depth in the tree
can be considered in any order by rotating
\index{rotation, in subgoal package} through them, but one
otherwise has to work through the tree depth first.
When a tactic solves a
subgoal (\ie\ returns an empty subgoal list), then the package computes
a part of the proof, and presents the user with the next subgoal.

For many users, the subgoal package
\index{subgoal package!as HOL interface@as \HOL\ interface} is the
primary interface to \HOL\ for proving theorems.  As mentioned, it is
very convenient to be relieved of all the book-keeping labour.
However, there is some cost in that the subgoal-proof tree
\index{subgoal tree!in subgoal package} cannot be inspected;
it only exists ephemerally for the user during an interaction,
and can only be viewed at the current top subgoal of the stack.
Achieving-theorems are only displayed at the moment they are proved;
there is no naming or preserving of subgoals or justifications.
If there is any reason to view
other subgoals, this can only be accomplished by undoing segments of
the proof effort (backing up). Likewise, intermediate achieving-theorems
cannot be inspected after they have been displayed at proof time.  One
situation in which it is necessary
to have the tree available is in the debugging
\index{debugging, of tactics} of tactics written
by the user directly in \ML. It is planned in future versions of
\HOL\ to implement a more sophisticated subgoal management package.

Finally, the application of certain tactics to certain goals generates
a failure
\index{failure, of tactics|)}
in \ML\, where the tactic is invalid; this does not happen when
using \HOL\ directly.

The example from earlier is continued below.  In the session below,
the conjunction proof is generated again, but using the subgoal
package, in which a goal is `set' using the function \ml{set\_goal}\index{side effects, in subgoal package}
and `expanded' using the function \ml{expand}. The side effects of
these functions on the subgoal package's stacks can be inferred.


\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#set_goal([],"(HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])");;
"(HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])"

() : void

#expand CONJ_TAC;;
OK..
2 subgoals
"TL[1;2;3] = [2;3]"

"HD[1;2;3] = 1"

() : void

#expand(REWRITE_TAC[HD;TL]);;
OK..
goal proved
|- HD[1;2;3] = 1

Previous subproof:
"TL[1;2;3] = [2;3]"

() : void

#expand(REWRITE_TAC[HD;TL]);;
OK..
goal proved
|- TL[1;2;3] = [2;3]
|- (HD[1;2;3] = 1) /\ (TL[1;2;3] = [2;3])
\end{verbatim}\end{session}


The following functions
\index{subgoal package!functions of|(} are available for interacting
with the subgoal package. The function

\index{set_goal@\ml{set\_goal}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   set_goal: goal -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent initializes the subgoal package with a new goal.

The function

\index{expand@\ml{expand}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   expand : tactic -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent applies a tactic to the top goal on the stack, then pushes the resulting
subgoals onto the goal stack and prints them. If there are no
resulting subgoals (\ie\ if the current goal was just solved), then
the appropriate proof function 
is applied to the empty list of theorems and the resulting theorems are printed.

The function

\index{backup@\ml{backup}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   backup : void -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent allows backing up from last state-change.  The assignable variable
\ml{backup\_limit},
\index{backup_limit@\ml{backup\_limit}}
initially set to \ml{12}, determines the maximum number 
of proof states saved
on the backup list.  The function \ml{backup} can be repeated until the list is
exhausted; backing up discards the current state irretrievably.

The function

\index{rotate@\ml{rotate}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   rotate : int -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent rotates\index{rotation, in subgoal package} the order of subgoals on the stack.  Calling
\ml{rotate} on $n$
rotates by $n$ steps the set of subgoals on top of the 
stack.  This enables
subgoals at a given depth
in the subgoal tree to 
be considered in any order.  However, subgoals deeper in the stack
cannot be worked on, nor can subgoals higher in the tree.

The function

\index{top_goal@\ml{top\_goal}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   top_goal : void -> goal
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent returns the top goal on the stack.

The function

\index{top_thm@\ml{top\_thm}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   top_thm : * -> thm
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent returns the theorem on top of the theorem stack. It is used
to access the result of an interactive proof session
with the subgoal package.

The function

\index{save_top_thm@\ml{save\_top\_thm}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   save_top_thm : string -> thm
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}


\noindent saves the top theorem on the goal stack in
the current theory, and also returns it as a value.
(It is
generally used only to save the final theorem, 
rather than the intermediate theorems in the
proof search.)

The function

\index{get_state@\ml{get\_state}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   get_state : void -> goalstack
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent returns the current proof state, which can then be 
assigned to a variable
for additional backup.

The function

\index{set_state@\ml{set\_state}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   set_state : goalstack -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent restores the proof state to that saved earlier using \ml{get\_state}.

The function

\index{print_state@\ml{print\_state}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   print_state : int -> void
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}
applied to $n$, prints $n$ levels of the goal stack.

The following abbreviations are pre-declared for use in the subgoal package:

\index{g, the subgoal package function@\ml{g}, the subgoal package function}
\index{e, the subgoal package function@\ml{e}, the subgoal package function}
\index{p, the subgoal package function@\ml{p}, the subgoal package function}
\index{b, the subgoal package function@\ml{b}, the subgoal package function}
\index{r, the subgoal package function@\ml{r}, the subgoal package function}
\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   let g t = set_goal([],t)
   and e   = expand
   and p   = print_state
   and b   = backup
   and r   = rotate;;
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\index{flags, for subgoal package}\index{subgoal package!flags for}
The flag \ml{print\_all\_subgoals} affects all operations where the subgoal
stack is printed.  If the flag is \ml{true}, the entire subgoal stack is
printed.  If the flag is \ml{false}, only the top subgoal on the stack is
printed. If only the current subgoal is to be printed, the subgoal package
will report the number of subgoals remaining before displaying the subgoal
on the top of the goal stack.  The default value of this flag is \ml{true}.
\index{subgoal package!functions of|)}

\section{Some tactics built into HOL}
\label{avra_builtin}

This section contains a
selection of the more commonly
\index{tactics!list of some|(}
 used tactics in the \HOL\ system. (see
\REFERENCE\
for the complete list, with fuller explanations.)

It should be recalled that the \ML\ type {\small\verb%thm_tactic%} 
abbreviates {\small\verb%thm->tactic%}, 
and the type {\small\verb%conv%}
abbreviates \ml{term->thm}.

\subsection{Acceptance of a theorem}


\begin{boxed}\index{ACCEPT_TAC@\ml{ACCEPT\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{verbatim}
   ACCEPT_TAC : thm_tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} {\small\verb%ACCEPT_TAC %}$th$ 
is a tactic that solves any goal that is 
achieved by $th$.

\index{forward proof!interfacing to goal directed}
\item{\bf  Use:} Incorporating forward proofs, or theorems already
proved, into goal directed proofs.
For example, one might reduce a goal $g$ to 
subgoals $g_1$, $\dots$, $g_n$ 
using a tactic $T$ and then prove theorems $th_1$ , $\dots$, $th_n$ 
respectively achieving 
these goals by forward proof. The tactic

\[\ml{  T THENL[ACCEPT\_TAC }th_1\ml{;}\ldots\ml{;ACCEPT\_TAC }th_n\ml{]}
\]

would then solve $g$, where \ml{THENL}
\index{THENL@\ml{THENL}} is the tactical that applies
the respective elements of the tactic list to the subgoals produced
by \ml{T} (see Section~\ref{avra_thenl}).

\end{itemize}


\subsection{Adding an assumption}

\index{ASSUME_TAC@\ml{ASSUME\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   ASSUME_TAC : thm_tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item {\bf Summary:} {\small\verb%ASSUME_TAC |-%}$u$ adds $u$ as an assumption.
\index{assumptions!tactic for adding}
 
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$t$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{u\}t$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
   
\item{\bf Use:} Enriching the assumptions of a goal 
with definitions or previously proved theorems.

\end{itemize}

\subsection{Specialization}\index{universal quantifier, in HOL logic@universal quantifier, in \HOL\ logic!tactics for}

\index{GEN_TAC@\ml{GEN\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   GEN_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\index{specialization tactic}
\item{\bf  Summary:} Specializes a universally quantified
theorem to an arbitrary value.
   

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
{\small\verb%!%}$x${\small\verb%.%}$t[x]$
\\ \hline \hline
$t[x']$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent where $x'$ is a variant of $x$ 
not free in either goal or assumptions.

\item{\bf   Use:} Solving universally quantified goals. 
\ml{GEN\_TAC} is often the first step of a goal directed proof.
{\small\verb%STRIP_TAC%} (see below) 
applies {\small\verb%GEN_TAC%} to universally quantified goals.
\end{itemize}

\subsection{Conjunction}

\index{CONJ_TAC@\ml{CONJ\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   CONJ_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\index{conjunction, in HOL logic@conjunction, in \HOL\ logic!tactic for splitting of}
\item{\bf Summary:} Splits a 
goal $t_1${\small\verb%/\%}$t_2$ into two 
subgoals, $t_1$ and $t_2$.

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$t_1${\small\verb% /\ %}$t_2$
\\ \hline \hline
$t_1\ \ \ \ \ \ t_2$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\item{\bf Use:} Solving conjunctive goals. 
{\small\verb%CONJ_TAC%} is invoked by {\small\verb%STRIP_TAC%} (see below).

\end{itemize}

\subsection{Discharging an assumption}
\label{avradisch}

\index{implication, in HOL logic@implication, in \HOL\ logic!tactics for}
\index{DISCH_TAC@\ml{DISCH\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   DISCH_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} Moves the antecedant 
of an implicative goal into the assumptions, leaving the consequent
as the term component.

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$u${\small\verb% ==> %}$v$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{u\}v$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}


\item{\bf Use:} Solving goals of the form 
$u${\small\verb% ==> %}$v$ 
by assuming $u$  and then solving
$v$ under the assumption.
{\small\verb%STRIP_TAC%} (see below) invokes 
{\small\verb%DISCH_TAC%} on implicative goals.
\end{itemize}

\subsection{Combined simple decompositions}

\index{STRIP_TAC@\ml{STRIP\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   STRIP_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} Breaks a goal apart.
{\small\verb%STRIP_TAC%} removes one outer connective from the goal, using
{\small\verb%CONJ_TAC%}, {\small\verb%DISCH_TAC%}, {\small\verb%GEN_TAC%},
and other tactics.
If the goal has the form $t_1${\small\verb%/\%}$\cdots${\small\verb%/\%}$t_n${\small\verb% ==> %}$t$
then {\small\verb%DISCH_TAC%} makes each $t_i$ into a separate assumption.

\item{\bf Use:} Useful for splitting a goal up into manageable pieces. 
Often the best thing to do first is {\small\verb%REPEAT STRIP_TAC%},
where \ml{REPEAT} is the tactical that repeatedly applies a tactic
until it fails (see Section~\ref{avra_repeat}).
\end{itemize}



\subsection{Substitution}

\index{SUBST_TAC@\ml{SUBST\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   SUBST_TAC : thm list -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:}
{\small\verb%SUBST_TAC[|-%}$u_1${\small\verb%=%}$v_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;|-%}$u_n${\small\verb%=%}$v_n${\small\verb%]%}
changes\index{substitution, tactic for} each sub-term
$t[u_1,\ldots ,u_n]$ of the goal to
$t[v_1,\ldots ,v_n]$
by substitution.

\item{\bf Use:} 
Useful in situations where {\small\verb%REWRITE_TAC%}
\index{REWRITE_TAC@\ml{REWRITE\_TAC}} does too much,
or would loop.
\end{itemize}


\subsection{Case analysis on a boolean term}
\index{case analysis, in HOL logic@case analysis, in \HOL\ logic!tactics for|(}

\index{ASM_CASES_TAC@\ml{ASM\_CASES\_TAC}|(}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   ASM_CASES_TAC : term -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} \ml{ASM\_CASES\_TAC} $u$ , where $u$ is a
boolean-valued term, does case analysis on $u$.

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$t$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{u\}t\ \ \ \ \ \{${\small\verb%~%}$u\}t$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\item{\bf Use:} Case analysis. 
\end{itemize}
\index{ASM_CASES_TAC@\ml{ASM\_CASES\_TAC}|)}

\subsection{Case analysis on a disjunction}


\begin{boxed}
\index{DISJ_CASES_TAC@\ml{DISJ\_CASES\_TAC}|pin}
\index{disjunction, in HOL logic@disjunction, in \HOL\ logic!tactic for case splits on}
\begin{verbatim}
   DISJ_CASES_TAC : thm_tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} 
{\small\verb%DISJ_CASES_TAC |- %}$u${\small\verb% \/ %}$v$  
splits a goal into two cases: one with $u$
as an assumption
and the other with $v$ as an assumption.

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$t$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{u\}t\ \ \ \ \ \{v\}t$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\item{\bf Use:} Case analysis. The 
tactic {\small\verb%ASM_CASES_TAC%} is defined in \ML\ by

{\small\begin{verbatim}
   let ASM_CASES_TAC t = DISJ_CASES_TAC(SPEC t EXCLUDED_MIDDLE)
\end{verbatim}}


\noindent where {\small\verb%EXCLUDED_MIDDLE%} is 
the theorem {\small\verb%|- !t. t \/ ~t%}.

\end{itemize}
\index{case analysis, in HOL logic@case analysis, in \HOL\ logic!tactics for|)}

\subsection{Rewriting}
\label{rewrite}

\index{rewriting!main tactic for|(}
\begin{boxed}
\index{REWRITE_TAC@\ml{REWRITE\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{verbatim}
   REWRITE_TAC : thm list -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}


\begin{itemize}
\item{\bf Summary:} {\small\verb%REWRITE_TAC[%}$th_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;%}$th_n${\small\verb%]%} 
transforms the term part of a goal by rewriting
it with the given theorems $th_1$, $\dots$, $th_n$, 
and the set of pre-proved standard tautologies\index{tautologies, in rewriting tactic}.


\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$\{t_1, \ldots , t_m\}t$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{t_1, \ldots , t_m\}t'$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent where $t'$ is obtained from $t$ as described.

\item{\bf Use:} Advancing goals by using definitions and
previously proved theorems (lemmas).\index{lemmas}


\item{\bf Some other rewriting tactics} (based on {\small\verb%REWRITE_TAC%}) are:
\begin{enumerate}
\item {\small\verb%ASM_REWRITE_TAC%}\index{ASM_REWRITE_TAC@\ml{ASM\_REWRITE\_TAC}}
 adds the assumptions of the goal to the list of
theorems used for rewriting.
\index{PURE_ASM_REWRITE_TAC@\ml{PURE\_ASM\_REWRITE\_TAC}}
\item {\small\verb%PURE_ASM_REWRITE_TAC%} is like {\small\verb%ASM_REWRITE_TAC%}, but it
doesn't use any built-in rewrites.
\index{PURE_REWRITE_TAC@\ml{PURE\_REWRITE\_TAC}}
\item {\small\verb%PURE_REWRITE_TAC%} uses neither the assumptions nor the built-in rewrites.
\index{FILTER_ASM_REWRITE_TAC@\ml{FILTER\_ASM\_REWRITE\_TAC}}
\item {\small\verb%FILTER_ASM_REWRITE_TAC %}$p${\small\verb% [%}$th_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;%}$th_n${\small\verb%]%} 
simplifies the goal by rewriting
it with the explicitly given theorems $th_1$ , $\dots$, $th_n$ , 
together with those
assumptions of the goal which satisfy the predicate $p$ and also
the standard rewrites.

\end{enumerate}
\end{itemize}

\index{rewriting!main tactic for|)}


\subsection{Resolution by Modus Ponens}

\index{implication, in HOL logic@implication, in \HOL\ logic!tactics for}
\index{IMP_RES_TAC@\ml{IMP\_RES\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   IMP_RES_TAC : thm -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\index{resolution tactics}
\item{\bf Summary:} {\small\verb%IMP_RES_TAC %}$th$ does a limited amount of
automated theorem proving in the form of forward inference; it
`resolves' the theorem $th$ with the 
assumptions of the goal
and adds any new results to the assumptions. The specification for
\ml{IMP\_RES\_TAC} is:


\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$\{t_1,\ldots,t_m\}t$
\\ \hline \hline
$\{t_1,\ldots,t_m,u_1,\ldots,u_n\}t$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\noindent  where $u_1$, $\dots$, $u_n$ 
are derived by `resolving' the theorem $th$ with the existing assumptions 
$t_1$, $\dots$, $t_m$. 
Resolution in \HOL\ is not classical resolution, but just Modus Ponens with
one-way pattern matching (not unification) and term and type instantiation. The
general case is where $th$ is of the canonical form

$\ \ \ ${\small\verb%|- !%}$x_1$$\ldots x_p${\small\verb%.%}$v_1$ {\small\verb%==>%} $v_2$ {\small\verb%==>%} $\ldots$ {\small\verb%==>%} $v_q$ {\small\verb%==>%} $v$

\noindent {\small\verb%IMP_RES_TAC %}$th$ then tries to specialize $x_1$,
$\dots$, $x_p$ in succession so that $v_1$, $\dots$, $v_q$ match members of
$\{t_1,\ldots ,t_m\}$.  Each time a match is found for some antecedent $v_i$,
for $i$ successively equal to $1$, $2$, \dots, $q$, a term and type
instantiation is made and the rule of Modus Ponens is applied.  If all the
antecedents $v_i$ (for $1 \leq i \leq q$) can be dismissed in this way, then
the appropriate instance of $v$ is added to the assumptions. Otherwise, if only
some initial sequence $v_1$, \dots, $v_k$ (for some $k$ where $1 < k < q$) of
the assumptions can be dismissed, then the remaining implication:

$\ \ \ ${\small\verb%|- %} $v_{k+1}$ {\small\verb%==>%} $\ldots$ {\small\verb%==>%} $v_q$ {\small\verb%==>%} $v$

\noindent is added to the assumptions.

For a more detailed description of resolution and \ml{IMP\_RES\_TAC}, see
\REFERENCE.  (See also the Cambridge \LCF\ Manual \cite{new-LCF-man}.)

\item{\bf Use:} Deriving new results from a previously proved implicative
theorem, in combination with the current assumptions, so that subsequent
tactics can use these new results.  

\end{itemize}


        

\subsection{Identity}

\index{ALL_TAC@\ml{ALL\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   ALL_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}
\index{identity tactic}\index{tactics!identity for}
\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}}
\item{\bf Summary:} The identity tactic for the tactical {\small\verb%THEN%}
(see Section~\ref{tactics}). Useful for writing tactics.

\item{\bf Use:}
\begin{enumerate}
\index{REPEAT@\ml{REPEAT}}
\item Writing tacticals (see description of {\small\verb%REPEAT%} 
in Section~\ref{tacticals}).
\index{THENL@\ml{THENL}} 
\item With {\small\verb%THENL%} (see Section~\ref{avra_thenl}); 
for example, if tactic $T$ produces two subgoals 
$T_1$ is to be applied to the first while
nothing is to be done to the second,
then $T${\small\verb% THENL[%}$T_1${\small\verb%;ALL_TAC]%} is the
tactic required.
\end{enumerate}
\end{itemize}

\subsection{Null}

\index{NO_TAC@\ml{NO\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   NO_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}
\item{\bf Summary:} Tactic that always fails.

\item{\bf Use:} Writing tacticals.
\end{itemize}


\subsection{Splitting logical equivalences}


\begin{boxed}
\index{EQ_TAC@\ml{EQ\_TAC}|pin}
\index{equality, in HOL logic@equality, in \HOL\ logic!tactic for splitting}
\begin{verbatim}
   EQ_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} 
{\small\verb%EQ_TAC%}
splits an equational goal into two implications (the `if-case' and
the `only-if' case):

\begin{center}



\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$u\ \ml{=}\ v$
\\ \hline \hline
$u\ \ml{==>}\ v\ \ \ \ \ v\ \ml{==>}\ u$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\item{\bf Use:} Proving logical equivalences, \ie\ goals of the form
``$u$\ml{=}$v$'' where $u$ and $v$ are boolean terms.

\end{itemize}

\subsection{Solving existential goals}


\begin{boxed}
\index{EXISTS_TAC@\ml{EXISTS\_TAC}|pin}
\index{existential quantifier, in HOL logic@existential quantifier, in \HOL\ logic!tactic for}
\begin{verbatim}
   EXISTS_TAC : term -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\begin{itemize}

\item{\bf Summary:} 
{\small\verb%EXISTS_TAC "%}$u${\small\verb%"%}
reduces an existential goal {\small\verb%!%}$x${\small\verb%. %}$t[x]$
to the subgoal $t[u]$.

\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{c} \\
$\ml{!}x\ml{.} t[x]$
\\ \hline \hline
$t[u]$
\\
\end{tabular}
\end{center}

\item{\bf Use:} Proving existential goals.

\item{\bf Comment:} \ml{EXISTS\_TAC} is a crude way of solving
existential goals, but it is the only built-in tactic for this
purpose.  A more powerful approach uses Prolog-style `logic variables'
(\ie\ meta-variables)
that can be progressively refined towards the eventual witness.
Implementing this requires goals to contain an environment giving the binding
of logic variables to terms. Details (in the context of \LCF) are given 
in a  paper by Stefan Soko\l owski \cite{Stefan}.

\end{itemize}
\index{tactics!list of some|)}

\section{Tacticals}
\label{tacticals}

\index{tactics!tacticals for|(}
\index{tacticals|(}
\index{tacticals!list of some|(}
\index{tacticals!purpose of}
A {\it tactical\/} is not represented by a single \ML\ type,
but is in general
an \ML\ function that returns a tactic (or tactics) as result.
Tacticals may take parameters, and this is reflected in the variety of
\ML\ types that the built-in tacticals have. 
Tacticals are used for building compound tactics.\index{compound tactics, in HOL system@compound tactics, in \HOL\ system}
\index{tactics!compound}
Some important tacticals in 
the \HOL\ system
are listed below.
For a complete list of the tacticals in \HOL\ see \REFERENCE.

\subsection{Alternation}\index{alternation!of tactics|(}\index{tactics!alternation of}

\index{ORELSE@\ml{ORELSE}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   ORELSE : tactic -> tactic -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}


The tactical {\small\verb%ORELSE%} 
is an \ML\ infix. If $T_1$ and $T_2$ are tactics, 
\index{tacticals!for alternation}
then the \ML\ expression $T_1${\small\verb% ORELSE %}$T_2$ 
evaluates to a tactic which applies $T_1$ unless that fails;
if it fails,
it applies $T_2$. \ml{ORELSE} is defined in \ML\ 
as a curried infix by

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   (T1 ORELSE T2) g =  T1 g ? T2 g 
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}\index{alternation!of tactics|)}


\subsection{First success}

\index{FIRST@\ml{FIRST}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   FIRST : tactic list -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

The tactical \ml{FIRST} applies the first tactic, in a list
of tactics, that succeeds.

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   FIRST [\(T\sb{1}\);\(T\sb{2}\);\(\ldots\);\(T\sb{n}\)] = \(T\sb{1}\) ORELSE \(T\sb{2}\) ORELSE \(\ldots\) ORELSE \(T\sb{n}\)
\end{alltt}\end{hol}



\subsection{Change detection}

\index{CHANGED_TAC@\ml{CHANGED\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   CHANGED_TAC : tactic -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}


\ml{CHANGED\_TAC\ $T$\ $g$} fails if the subgoals
produced by $T$ are just \ml{[$g$]}; otherwise it is equivalent
to $T\ g$. It is defined by the following, where
{\small\verb%set_equal : * list -> * list -> bool%} tests whether two lists
denote the same set (\ie\ contain the same elements).


\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   letrec CHANGED_TAC tac g =
    let gl,p = tac g in
    if set_equal gl [g] then fail else (gl,p)
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}



\subsection{Sequencing}
\index{sequencing!of tactics|(}
\index{tacticals!for sequencing|(}
\index{tactics!sequencing of|(}
\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}!ML implementation of@\ML\ implementation of|(}

\begin{boxed}\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}|pin}
\begin{verbatim}
   THEN : tactic -> tactic -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}


The tactical {\small\verb%THEN%} is an \ML\ infix. If $T_1$ and $T_2$ are tactics,
then the \ML\ expression $T_1${\small\verb% THEN %}$T_2$ evaluates to a tactic
which first applies $T_1$ and then applies $T_2$ to each subgoal produced by
$T_1$. Its definition
 in \ML\ is complex (and due to Milner)\index{Milner, R.} but worth
understanding as an exercise in \ML.  It is an \ML\ curried infix.

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   let ((T1:tactic) THEN (T2:tactic)) g =
    let gl,p = T1 g
    in
    let gll,pl = split(map T2 gl) 
    in
    (flat gll, (p o mapshape(map length gll)pl));;
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent Some of the \ML\ functions \ml{map}, \ml{split}, \ml{o}, \ml{length}, 
\ml{flat} and \ml{mapshape} were introduced in Chapter~\ref{MLfuns}. Here are
their definitions:

%\begin{itemize}
\bigskip

\index{map@\ml{map}}
{\small\verb%map : (* -> **) -> * list -> ** list%}

\medskip

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   map \(f\) [\(x\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(x\sb{n}\)]  =  [\(f\) \(x\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(f\) \(x\sb{n}\)]
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\medskip

\index{split@\ml{split}}
{\small\verb%split : (* # **) list -> (* list # ** list)%}

\medskip

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}\   split[(\(x\sb{1}\),\(y\sb{1}\));\(\ldots\);(\(x\sb{n}\),\(y\sb{n}\))]  =  ([\(x\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(x\sb{n}\)],[\(y\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(y\sb{n}\)])
\end{alltt}\end{hol}


\medskip

{\small\verb%$o : ((* -> **) # (*** -> *)) -> *** -> **$%}
 (an infix)\index{function composition, in ML@function composition, in \ML}

\medskip

\begin{hol}
\begin{alltt}
   (\(f\) o \(g\)) \(x\)  =  \(f\)(\(g\) \(x\))
\end{alltt}\end{hol}
\index{ function composition operator, in ML@{\small\verb+o+} (function composition operator, in \ML)}

\medskip

\index{length@\ml{length}}
{\small\verb%length : * list -> int%}

\medskip

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   length[\(x\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(x\sb{n}\)]  =  n
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\medskip


{\small\verb%flat : (* list) list -> * list%}\index{flat@\ml{flat}}


\medskip

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   flat[[\({x\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\)];[\({x\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\)];\(\ldots\);[\({x\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)]] =
    [\({x\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\); \(\ldots\) ;\({x\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)]
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\medskip

{\small\verb%mapshape : int list -> (* list -> **) list -> * list -> **
list%}\index{mapshape@\ml{mapshape}}


\medskip

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   mapshape
    [\(m\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(m\sb{n}\)]
    [\(f\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(f\sb{n}\)]
    [\({x\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\); \(\ldots\) ;\({x\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)] =
   [\(f\sb{1}\)[\({x\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\)];\(f\sb{2}\)[\({x\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\)]; \(\ldots\) ;\(f\sb{n}\)[\({x\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({x\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)]]
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

%\end{itemize}

\bigskip

Suppose \ml{$T_1\ g$ = ($gl$,$p$)} where \ml{$gl$=[$g_1$;$\ldots$;$g_n$]}. 
Suppose also that
for $i$ between $1$ and $n$ it is the case that 
\ml{$T_2\ g_i$ = ([${g_i}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_i}_{m_i}$],$p_i$)}.
Then \ml{split(map $T_2$ $gl$)} will evaluate to the 
pair \ml{($gll$,$pl$)} of a subgoal list and a proof function, where

\bigskip

\ml{$gll$ = [[${g_1}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_1}_{m_1}$];[${g_2}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_2}_{m_2}$];
$\ \ldots\ $;[${g_n}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_n}_{m_n}$]]} 

\bigskip

\noindent and 
\ml{$pl$ = [$p_1$;$\ldots$;$p_n$]}. Note that 

\bigskip

\ml{map length $gll$ = [$m_1$;$\ldots$;$m_n$]} 

\bigskip

\noindent and that 

\bigskip

\ml{flat $gll$ = [${g_1}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_1}_{m_1}$;${g_2}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_2}_{m_2}$;
$\ \ldots\ $;${g_n}_1$;$\ldots$;${g_n}_{m_n}$]}

\bigskip

Suppose now that, for $i$ between $1$ and $n$, the theorems 
${th_i}_1$, $\dots$, ${th_i}_{m_i}$ achieve
the goals ${g_i}_1$, $\dots$, ${g_i}_{m_i}$, respectively. 
It will follow that if $T_2$ is valid
then for $i$ between $1$ and $n$ 
the result of applying $p_i$ to the list of 
theorems \ml{[${th_i}_1$;$\ldots$;${th_i}_{m_i}$]} 
will be a theorem, $th_i$ say, which achieves 
$g_i$. 
Now if $T_1$ is valid then \ml{$p$[$th_1$;$\ldots$;$th_n$]} 
will evaluate to a theorem, 
$th$ say,
that achieves the goal $g$. Thus

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
    \(p\)
    (mapshape
     (map length \(gll\))
     \(pl\)
     [\({th\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\);\({th\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\);\(\ \ldots\ \) ;\({th\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)]) =

    \(p\)([\(p\sb{1}\)[\({th\sb{1}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{1}}\sb{m\sb{1}}\)];\(p\sb{2}\)[\({th\sb{2}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{2}}\sb{m\sb{2}}\)];\(\ \ldots\ \);\(p\sb{n}\)[\({th\sb{n}}\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\({th\sb{n}}\sb{m\sb{n}}\)]]) =

    \(p\)([\(th\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(th\sb{n}\)]) = 

    \(th\)
\end{alltt}\end{hol}
 
This shows that
\index{justifications, in goal-directed proof search!THEN example of@\ml{THEN} example of}
\index{proof functions (same as justifications, validations)!THEN example of@\ml{THEN} example of}
\ml{$p$ o mapshape(map length $gll$)$pl$} 
is a function that, when
applied to a list of theorems respectively
achieving \ml{flat $gll$}, returns a theorem
(namely $th$) that achieves $g$.\index{sequencing!of tactics|)}
\index{tacticals!for sequencing|)}
\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}!ML implementation of@\ML\ implementation of|)}

\subsection{Selective sequencing}

\index{THENL@\ml{THENL}}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   THENL : tactic -> tactic list -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}
\label{avra_thenl}

\index{selective sequencing tactical}
If tactic $T$ produces $n$ subgoals and $T_1$, $\dots$,
$T_n$ are tactics
then $T${\small\verb% THENL [%}$T_1${\small\verb%;%}$\ldots${\small\verb%;%}$T_n${\small\verb%]%} 
is a tactic which first applies $T$ and then
applies $T_i$ to the $i$th subgoal produced by $T$. 
The tactical {\small\verb%THENL%} is useful if one wants to apply different
tactics to different subgoals.

Here is the definition of \ml{THENL}:

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
      let ((T:tactic) THENL (Tl:tactic list)) g =
       let gl,p = T g  
       in
       let gll,pl = (split(map (\(T,g). T g) Tgl)
                      where Tgl = combine(Tl,gl) ? failwith `THENL`)
       in
       (flat gll, (p o mapshape(map length gll)pl))
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent The understanding of this procedure is left as an exercise!\index{tactics!sequencing of|)}

\subsection{Successive application}



\begin{boxed}
\index{EVERY, the ML function@\ml{EVERY}, the \ML\ function|pin}
\begin{verbatim}
   EVERY : tactic list -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\index{tacticals!for successive application}
\index{successive application!tactical for}
The tactical \ml{EVERY} applies a list of tactics one after the other.


\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   EVERY [\(T\sb{1}\);\(T\sb{2}\);\(\ldots\);\(T\sb{n}\)] = \(T\sb{1}\) THEN \(T\sb{2}\) THEN \(\ldots\) THEN \(T\sb{n}\)
\end{alltt}\end{hol}



\subsection{Repetition}

\begin{boxed}\index{REPEAT@\ml{REPEAT}|pin}
\begin{verbatim}
   REPEAT : tactic -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}
\label{avra_repeat}

If $T$ is a 
tactic then {\small\verb%REPEAT %}$T$ is a tactic\index{tactics!repetition of}
\index{tacticals!for repetition}\index{repetition!of tactics}
that repeatedly applies
$T$ until it fails. It is defined in \ML\ by:

{\small\baselineskip\HOLSpacing\begin{verbatim}
   letrec REPEAT T g = ((T THEN REPEAT T) ORELSE ALL_TAC) g
\end{verbatim}}

\noindent (The extra argument {\small\verb%g%} is needed because \ML\ does not use
lazy evaluation.)
\index{tacticals|)}
\index{tacticals!list of some|)}
\index{tactics!tacticals for|)}

\section{Tactics for manipulating assumptions}
\label{asm-manip}

\index{tactics!for manipulating assumptions|(}
There are in general two kinds of tactics\index{tactics!term transforming}\index{tactics!assumption transforming}
 in \HOL: those that transform the
conclusion of a goal without affecting the assumptions, and those that
do (also or only) affect the assumptions.  The various tactics that
rewrite\index{rewriting!main tactic for}
 are typical of the first class; those that do `resolution'
\index{resolution tactics} belong to
the second.  Often, many of the steps of a proof in \HOL\ are carried
out `behind the scenes' on the assumptions, by tactics of the second sort.
A tactic that in some way changes the assumptions must also have a
justification that `knows how' to restore the corresponding hypotheses of
the theorem achieving the subgoal. All of this is explicit, and can be
examined by a user moving about the subgoal-proof tree.\footnote{The current
subgoal package makes this difficult, but the point still holds.}
Using these tactics in the most straightforward way, the assumptions at any
point in a goal-directed proof, \ie\ at any node in the subgoal tree,
\index{subgoal tree!in proof construction}
\index{tree of subgoals, in proof construction} form
an unordered record of every assumption made, but not yet dismissed, up to that
point.

In practice, the straightforward use of assumption-changing
\index{assumptions!role of, in goal directed proof}
tactics,
with the tools currently provided in \HOL, presents at
least two difficulties.  The first is that assumption sets can grow to an
unwieldy size, the number and/or length of terms making them difficult to
read.  In addition, forward-search tactics such as resolution often add at least
some assumptions that are never subsequently used, and these have to be
carried along with the useful assumptions; the straightforward
method provides no ready way of intercepting their arrival.
Likewise, there is no straightforward way of discarding
\index{discarding assumptions}
\index{assumptions!discarding of, in proofs}
assumptions after they have been used and are merely adding to the clutter.
Although perhaps against the straightforward spirit, this is a perfectly valid
strategy, and
requires no more than a way of denoting 
the specific assumptions to be discarded. That, however,
raises the more general problem of denoting\index{assumptions!denoting of, in proofs}\index{denoting assumptions} assumptions in the first place.
Assumptions are also denoted
so that they can be
manipulated: given as parameters, combined to draw inferences, \etc\  The only
straightforward way to denote them in the existing system is to supply
their quoted text.  Though adequate, this 
method may result in bulky \ML\ expressions; and it may take some effort to present the text
correctly (with necessary type information, \etc).

As always in \HOL, there are quite a few ways around the various difficulties.
One approach, of course, is the one intended in the original 
design of\index{LCF@\LCF!Edinburgh} Edinburgh \LCF,
and advocates the rationale for providing a full programming language, \ML,
\index{ML@\ML!purpose of, in HOL system@purpose of, in \HOL\ system} 
rather than a simple proof command set: that is for the user to
implement new tactics in \ML.  For example, resolution tactics can be adapted
by the user to add new assumptions more selectively; and case analysis tactics
to make direct replacements without adding case assumptions.
This, again, is adequate, but can involve the user in extensive amounts of
programming, and in debugging exercises for which there is no
system support.

Short of implementing new tactics, two other standard
approaches are reflected in the current system.  Both were originally
developed for Cambridge \LCF\ \cite{lcp_rewrite,new-LCF-man}; both reflect
fresh views of the assumptions; and both rely on tacticals\index{tacticals!purpose of} that transform
tactics.  The two approaches are 
partly but not completely complementary.  

The first
approach, described in this section, implicitly regards the assumption
set, already represented as a list, as a stack, with a {\it pop\/}
operation, so that the assumption at the top of the stack can be (i) discarded
and (ii) denoted without explicit quotation.  (The corresponding {\it push\/}
adds new assumptions at the head of the list.)
The stack can be generalized to an array to allow for access to
arbitrary assumptions.

The other approach, described in Section~\ref{tacont},
gives a way of intercepting and manipulating results without them necessarily
being added as assumptions in the first place.  The two approaches can
be combined in \HOL\ interactions.


\subsection{Theorem continuations with popping}
\label{avra_manip1}

The first proof style, that of popping assumptions
\index{popping, of assumptions} from the assumption
`stack',\index{assumptions!as stack}
\index{stack, of assumptions} is illustrated using its main tool: the tactical
\ml{POP\_ASSUM}.\footnote{The type of {\tt POP\_ASSUM} is actually more general
than the type shown here. The present format is used simply for readability.}

\index{POP_ASSUM@\ml{POP\_ASSUM}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   POP_ASSUM : (thm -> tactic) -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent Given a function $f$\ml{:thm -> tactic}, the tactic
\ml{POP\_ASSUM}\ $f$ applies $f$ to the (assumed) first
assumption of a goal (\ie\ to the top element of the assumption stack)
and then applies the tactic created thereby to the original goal
minus its top assumption:

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   POP_ASSUM \(f\) ([\(t\sb{1}\);\(\ldots\);\(t\sb{n}\)],\(t\)) = \(f\) (ASSUME \(t\sb{1}\)) ([\(t\sb{2}\);\(\ldots\);\(t\sb{n}\)],\(t\))
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\noindent \ML\ functions such as $f$,
with type \ml{thm -> tactic}, abbreviated to \ml{thm\_tactic},
\index{thm_tactic@\ml{thm\_tactic}}
are called theorem continuations,
\index{theorem continuations} suggesting the fact that they
take theorems and then continue the proof.\footnote{There is a superficial analogy
with continuations in denotational semantics.}
The use of \ml{POP\_ASSUM}\ can be illustrated by applying it
to a particular tactic, namely \ml{DISCH\_TAC} (Section~\ref{avradisch}).

\index{DISCH_TAC@\ml{DISCH\_TAC}}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   DISCH_TAC : tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent On a goal whose
conclusion is an implication $u \imp v$, \ml{DISCH\_TAC} 
reflects the natural strategy of attempting to prove $v$ under the
assumption $u$, the discharged antecedent.
For example, suppose it were required to
prove that $(n = 0) \imp (n\times n = n)$:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e DISCH_TAC;;
OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "n = 0" ]
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent Application of \ml{DISCH\_TAC} to the goal produces one subgoal,
as shown, with the added assumption. To engage the assumption 
as a simple substitution, the tactic \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} is useful
(see \REFERENCE\ for details).


\index{SUBST1_TAC@\ml{SUBST1\_TAC}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   SUBST1_TAC : thm_tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} expects a theorem with an equational conclusion, and
substitutes accordingly, into the conclusion of the goal. At this
point in the session, the tactical
\ml{POP\_ASSUM} is applied to
\ml{SUBST1\_TAC} to form a new tactic.
The new tactic is applied to the current subgoal.

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#top_goal();;
(["n = 0"], "n * n = n") : goal

#e(POP_ASSUM SUBST1_TAC);;
OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The result, as shown, is that the assumption is used as a
substitution rule and then discarded.
\index{discarding assumptions}
\index{assumptions!discarding of, in proofs}
The one subgoal therefore has no
assumptions on its stack.  The two tactics used thus far could be combined
into one using the tactical \ml{THEN}:\index{THEN@\ml{THEN}}

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) ==> (n * n = 0)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_TAC THEN POP_ASSUM SUBST1_TAC);;
OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The goal can now be solved by rewriting with a fact of arithmetic:

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#e(REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]);;
Theorem MULT_CLAUSES autoloaded from theory `arithmetic`.
MULT_CLAUSES = 
|- !m n.
    (0 * m = 0) /\
    (m * 0 = 0) /\
    (1 * m = m) /\
    (m * 1 = m) /\
    ((SUC m) * n = (m * n) + n) /\
    (m * (SUC n) = m + (m * n))

OK..
goal proved
|- 0 * 0 = 0
|- (n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent A single tactic can, of course, be written to solve the goal:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_TAC THEN POP_ASSUM SUBST1_TAC THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]);;
Theorem MULT_CLAUSES autoloaded from theory `arithmetic`.
MULT_CLAUSES = 
|- !m n.
    (0 * m = 0) /\
    (m * 0 = 0) /\
    (1 * m = m) /\
    (m * 1 = m) /\
    ((SUC m) * n = (m * n) + n) /\
    (m * (SUC n) = m + (m * n))

OK..
goal proved
|- (n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

This example illustrates how the tactical \ml{POP\_ASSUM} provides
access\index{assumptions!denoting of, in proofs}
\index{denoting assumptions}
to the top of the assumption `stack' (a capability that
is useful, obviously, only when the
most recently pushed assumption is the very one required).
To accomplish this access in the straightforward way would
require some more awkward
\index{assumptions!explicit} construct, with explicit assumptions:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_TAC);;
OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "n = 0" ]

() : void

#e(SUBST1_TAC(ASSUME "n = 0"));;
OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
    [ "n = 0" ]
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

In contrast to the above, the popping example also illustrates the
convenient disappearance of an assumption no longer required, by removing it
from the stack at the moment when it is accessed and used. This is valid
because any theorem that achieves the subgoal
will still achieve the original goal. Discarding\index{discarding assumptions}\index{assumptions!discarding of, in proofs} assumptions
is a separate issue from accessing them;
there could, if one liked, be another
tactical that produced a similar tactic on a theorem continuation
to \ml{POP\_ASSUM} but which did not pop the
stack.

Finally, \ml{POP\_ASSUM} $f$ induces case splits where $f$ does.  To prove
$(n=0 \disj n=1) \imp (n\times n = n)$, the function \ml{DISJ\_CASES\_TAC}
can be used. The tactic

\ \ \ml{DISJ\_CASES\_TAC\ |- $p$}{\small\verb% \/ %}\ml{$q$}

\noindent splits a goal into two subgoals that have 
$p$ and $q$, respectively, as new assumptions.


\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "((n = 0) \/ (n = 1)) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) \/ (n = 1) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e DISCH_TAC;;
OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "(n = 0) \/ (n = 1)" ]

() : void

#backup();;
"(n = 0) \/ (n = 1) ==> (n * n = n)"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}
\vfill
\newpage
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#e(DISCH_TAC THEN POP_ASSUM DISJ_CASES_TAC);;
OK..
2 subgoals
"n * n = n"
    [ "n = 1" ]

"n * n = n"
    [ "n = 0" ]

() : void

#backup();;
"(n = 0) \/ (n = 1) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_TAC THEN POP_ASSUM DISJ_CASES_TAC THEN POP_ASSUM SUBST1_TAC);;
OK..
2 subgoals
"1 * 1 = 1"

"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

As noted earlier, \ml{POP\_ASSUM} is useful when an assumption
is required that is still at the top of the stack,
as in the examples.  However, it is often
necessary to access assumptions made at arbitrary previous times, in order to
give them as parameters, combine them, \etc\ The stack approach can be
extended to such cases by re-conceiving the stack as an array\index{assumptions!as array}\index{array, of assumptions}, and by
use of the tactical \ml{ASSUM\_LIST}:\index{ASSUM_LIST@\ml{ASSUM\_LIST}|(}

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   ASSUM_LIST : (thm list -> tactic ) -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent where

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   ASSUM_LIST \m{f} ([\m{t\sb{1}};...;\m{t\sb{n}}],\m{t}) = \m{f}([ASSUME \m{t\sb{1}};...;ASSUME \m{t\sb{n}}])
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\noindent That is, given a function $f$, \ml{ASSUM\_LIST}$\ f$ forms a new tactic
by applying $f$ to the list of (assumed) assumptions of a goal, then applies
the resulting tactic to the goal.  For example, a tactic of the form
{\small\verb%ASSUM_LIST (\thl.%}$\ f\ $\ml{(el\ $i$\ thl))} applies the
function $f$ to the $i$th assumption of a goal to produce a new tactic, then
applies the new tactic to the goal. 
Again, \ml{ASSUM\_LIST REWRITE\_TAC} is a tactic that engages all of the
current assumptions as rewrite rules.
In this way, the array approach
enables arbitrary assumptions to be accessed; and in particular,
specific assumptions to be accessed by location using the function \ml{el}.

To illustrate the use of \ml{ASSUM\_LIST}, suppose it were required to prove
something different: \index{ASSUM_LIST@\ml{ASSUM\_LIST}|)}
that $(\forall m.\ m + n = m) \imp (n \times n = n)$.  Suppose
also that the arithmetic fact \ml{ADD\_INV\_{0}} is already known: namely, that
$\forall m\ n.\ (m + n = m) \imp (n = 0)$. After discharging the assumption,
the conclusion of the theorem \ml{ADD\_INV\_{0}} is imported as an
assumption, occupying first place in the array.

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(!m. m + n = m) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(!m. m + n = m) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_TAC);;
OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "!m. m + n = m" ]

() : void

#e(ASSUME_TAC ADD_INV_0);;
Theorem ADD_INV_0 autoloaded from theory `arithmetic`.
ADD_INV_0 = |- !m n. (m + n = m) ==> (n = 0)

OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "!m. m + n = m" ]
    [ "!m n. (m + n = m) ==> (n = 0)" ]
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The problem is now to combine the two assumptions to produce the
obvious conclusion. That requires denoting
\index{denoting assumptions}
\index{assumptions!denoting of, in proofs} them, for which \ml{ASSUM\_LIST} 
provides the means. Finally,
\ml{ASSUME\_TAC} places the conclusion of the new result in the assumptions.
(The \ML\ function \ml{el: int -> * list -> *} is used here to select a
numbered element of a list.)

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#e(ASSUM_LIST(\thl. ASSUME_TAC
                       (MP (SPECL ["m:num";"n:num"] (el 1 thl)) 
                           (SPEC "m:num"(el 2 thl)))));;
##OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "!m. m + n = m" ]
    [ "!m n. (m + n = m) ==> (n = 0)" ]
    [ "n = 0" ]
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent The goal can now be solved as in the previous example. 

To access the
two particular assumptions in the straightforward way would again require quoting
their text. To access all of them (to pass to \ml{REWRITE\_TAC}, for
instance) would require quoting all of them.

\ml{ASSUM\_LIST} addresses the issue of accessing assumptions,
but not the issue of discarding them.  A related function generalizes
\ml{POP\_ASSUM} to discard them as well:

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   POP_ASSUM_LIST : (thm list -> tactic ) -> tactic
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent \ml{POP\_ASSUM\_LIST}
\index{POP_ASSUM_LIST@\ml{POP\_ASSUM\_LIST}}
resembles \ml{ASSUM\_LIST} except in removing
all of the old assumptions of the subgoal, the way that \ml{POP\_ASSUM}
removes the most recent.  (Thus \ml{POP\_ASSUM} is no more than a special case
of \ml{POP\_ASSUM\_LIST} that selects the first element of those supplied
and re-assumes the others.)

\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   POP_ASSUM_LIST \(f\) ([\(t\sb{1}\);\(\ \ldots\ \);\(t\sb{n}\)],\(t\)) =  \(f\) [ASSUME \(t\sb{1}\);\(\ \ldots\ \);ASSUME \(t\sb{n}\)] ([],t)
\end{alltt}\end{hol}

\noindent This is used when the existing assumptions have served
their purpose and can be discarded, as in the current example:

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#backup();;
"n * n = n"
    [ "!m. m + n = m" ]
    [ "!m n. (m + n = m) ==> (n = 0)" ]

() : void

#e(POP_ASSUM_LIST(\thl. ASSUME_TAC
                           (MP (SPECL ["m:num";"n:num"] (el 1 thl)) 
                               (SPEC "m:num"(el 2 thl)))));;
##OK..
"n * n = n"
    [ "n = 0" ]
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent This leaves only the one assumption vital to solving the goal,
as before. In some contexts, the new result is required as an assumption,
but here it can be used immediately:

\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#backup();;
"n * n = n"
    [ "!m. m + n = m" ]
    [ "!m n. (m + n = m) ==> (n = 0)" ]

() : void

#e(POP_ASSUM_LIST(\thl. SUBST1_TAC
                           (MP (SPECL ["m:num";"n:num"] (el 1 thl)) 
                               (SPEC "m:num"(el 2 thl)))));;
##OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent \ml{POP\_ASSUM\_LIST} can, of course, 
take any function of appropriate
type, but is in fact often used in conjunction with the element-selecting
functions. Function composition occasionally allows a more
compact expression to be written.

The array view (of which the stack view is a special case)
gives a way in which unnecessary assumptions can
be dropped, and assumptions can be accessed, individually if necessary,
using tacticals.
Although this approach can be effective, as illustrated, it does
tend to rely on the ordering of the representation of the assumption
\index{assumptions!importance of ordering of} set.
(That is, \ml{POP\_ASSUM} necessarily does, while the other two provide the
temptation!) A minor drawback of this reliance is that tactics are then
sensitive to changes that alter the order or composition of the assumptions;
for example, changes in the implementation of \HOL, modifications of
existing tactics, and so on.
However, that sensitivity is not so serious in any one incarnation of \HOL;
there is a logical viewpoint that regards the assumptions (sequents) as
ordered anyway.
A more serious problem is that order-sensitive tactics are meaningful
only during interactive sessions; to reconstruct the assumptions from
the \ML\ text and the original goal alone is generally difficult,
and more so when assumptions are denoted by location.
This means that (i) the resulting tactics cannot easily be generalized
for use in other contexts, and (ii) the \ML\ text does not supply
useful documentation
\index{tactics!as documentation of proofs} of the solution of the goal.
Also, as shown in the last example, it it slightly unsatisfactory
to push and subsequently pop assumptions, especially in immediate succession,
where this could be avoided.

Two other tacticals that can be used to manipulate the assumption list are
{\small\verb%FIRST_ASSUM%} and {\small\verb%EVERY_ASSUM%}.
These are characterized by:

\index{FIRST_ASSUM@\ml{FIRST\_ASSUM}}
\index{EVERY_ASSUM@\ml{EVERY\_ASSUM}}
\begin{hol}\begin{alltt}
   FIRST_ASSUM \(f\) ([\(t\sb{1}\); \(\ldots\) ;\(t\sb{n}\)], \(t\))  =
    (\(f\)(ASSUME \(t\sb{1}\)) ORELSE \(\ldots\) ORELSE \(f\)(ASSUME \(t\sb{n}\))) ([\(t\sb{1}\); \(\ldots\) ;\(t\sb{n}\)], \(t\))

   EVERY_ASSUM \(f\) ([\(t\sb{1}\); \(\ldots\) ;\(t\sb{n}\)], \(t\))  =  
    (\(f\)(ASSUME \(t\sb{1}\)) THEN \(\ldots\) THEN  \(f\)(ASSUME \(t\sb{n}\))) ([\(t\sb{1}\); \(\ldots\) ;\(t\sb{n}\)], \(t\))
\end{alltt}\end{hol}


\subsection{Theorem continuations without popping}
\label{tacont}

The idea of the second approach is suggested by the way the array-style
tacticals\index{tacticals!purpose of} supply a list of theorems (the assumed assumptions) 
to a function.  These tacticals use the function to
infer new 
results from the list of theorems, and then to do something with the
results. In some cases, 
\eg\ the last example, the assumptions need never have been made in the
first place, which suggests a different use of tacticals.
The original example for \ml{POP\_ASSUM}
illustrates this: namely, to show that $(n = 0) \imp (n\times n = n)$.  Here,
instead of discharging the antecedent by applying
\ml{DISCH\_TAC} to the goal, which adds the antecedent as an assumption
and returns the consequent as the conclusion,
and {\it then\/} supplying the (assumed) added assumption to the
theorem continuation \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} and
discarding it at the same time,
a tactical called \ml{DISCH\_THEN} is applied to \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} directly.
\ml{DISCH\_THEN} transforms \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} into
a new tactic: one that applies \ml{SUBST1\_TAC} directly to the (assumed)
antecedent, and the resulting tactic to a subgoal with no new
assumptions and the consequent as its conclusion:
\vfill
\newpage

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#DISCH_THEN;;
- : (thm_tactic -> tactic)

#DISCH_THEN SUBST1_TAC;;
- : tactic

#g "(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_THEN SUBST1_TAC);;
OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent This gives the same result as the stack method, but more
directly, with a more compact \ML\ expression,
and with the attractive feature that the term
$n=0$ is never an assumption, even for an interval of one step.
This technique is often used at the moment when results are available;
as above, where the result produced by discharging the antecedent can be
immediately passed to substitution. If the result were only needed
later, it {\it would\/} have to be held as an assumption. However, results
can be manipulated when they are available, and their results
either held as assumptions or used immediately.
For example, to prove $(0=n) \imp (n \times n = n)$, 
the result $n=0$ could be reversed
immediately:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "(0 = n) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(0 = n) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_THEN(SUBST1_TAC o SYM));;
OK..
"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

The justification of \ml{DISCH\_THEN SUBST1\_TAC} is easily constructed
from the justification of \ml{DISCH\_TAC} composed with the justification of
\ml{SUBST1\_TAC}. \index{assumptions!internal|(}
The term $n=0$ is assumed, to yield the
theorem that is passed to the theorem continuation \ml{SUBST1\_TAC},
and it is accordingly discharged during the construction of the
actual proof; but the assumption happens
only internally
\index{assumptions!internal|)} to the tactic \ml{DISCH\_THEN SUBST1\_TAC}, and not
as a step in the tactical proof.  In other words, the subgoal tree here
has one node fewer than before, when an explicit step (\ml{DISCH\_TAC}) 
reflected the assumption.

On the goal with the disjunctive antecedent, this method again
provides a compact tactic:

\setcounter{sessioncount}{1}
\begin{session}\begin{verbatim}
#g "((n = 0) \/ (n = 1)) ==> (n * n = n)";;
"(n = 0) \/ (n = 1) ==> (n * n = n)"

() : void

#e(DISCH_THEN(DISJ_CASES_THEN SUBST1_TAC));;
OK..
2 subgoals
"1 * 1 = 1"

"0 * 0 = 0"
\end{verbatim}\end{session}

\noindent This avoids the repeated popping and pushing of the stack
solution, and likewise, gives a shorter \ML\ expression. Both give
a shorter expression than the direct method, which is:

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   DISCH_TAC 
    THEN DISJ_CASES_TAC(ASSUME "(n = 0) \/ (n = 1)") 
    THENL[SUBST1_TAC(ASSUME "n = 0");
          SUBST1_TAC(ASSUME "n = 1")]
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

To summarize, there are so far at least five ways to solve a goal
(and these are often combined in one interaction):
directly, using the stack view of the assumptions,
using the array view with or without discarding assumptions, and using a
tactical to intercept an assumption step.  All of the following work
\index{assumptions!compared methods of handling}
on the goal $(n=0) \imp (n \times n = n)$:

\begin{hol}\index{ASSUM_LIST@\ml{ASSUM\_LIST}}
\begin{verbatim}
   DISCH_TAC 
    THEN SUBST1_TAC(ASSUME "n = 0") 
    THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]

   DISCH_TAC 
    THEN POP_ASSUM SUBST1_TAC 
    THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]

   DISCH_TAC 
    THEN ASSUM_LIST (SUBST1_TAC o el 1) 
    THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]

   DISCH_TAC 
    THEN POP_ASSUM_LIST (SUBST1_TAC o el 1) 
    THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]

   DISCH_THEN SUBST1_TAC 
    THEN REWRITE_TAC[MULT_CLAUSES]
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent Furthermore, all five induce the
same sequence of inferences leading to
the desired theorem; internally, no inference steps are saved by the
economies in the \ML\ text or the subgoal tree.  In this sense,
the choice is entirely one of style and taste;
of how to organize the decomposition into subgoals.
The first expression illustrates the verbosity of denoting
assumptions by text (the goal with the
disjunctive antecedent gave a clearer
example); but also
the intelligibility of the resulting expression, which, of course, is all
that is saved of the interaction, aside from the final theorem.
The last expression
illustrates both the elegance and the inscrutibility of
using functions to manipulate intermediate results directly, rather than
as assumptions.
The middle three expressions
show how results can be used as assumptions (discarded when
redundant, if desired); and how
assumptions can be denoted without
recourse to their text.
It is a strength of the \LCF\ approach
\index{LCF@\LCF} to
theorem proving that many different proof styles are supported,
(all in a secure way) and indeed, can be studied in their own
right.

\HOL\ provides several other theorem continuation functions analogous to
\ml{DISCH\_THEN} and \ml{DISJ\_CASES\_THEN}.
(Their names always end with
`\ml{\_THEN}', `\ml{\_THENL} or `\ml{\_THEN2}'.) 
Some of these do convenient inferences for the user.
For example:

\index{CHOOSE_THEN@\ml{CHOOSE\_THEN}|pin}
\begin{boxed}\begin{verbatim}
   CHOOSE_THEN : thm_tactical
\end{verbatim}\end{boxed}

\noindent Where \ml{thm\_tactical} abbreviates
{\small\verb%thm_tactic -> tactic%}.
\ml{CHOOSE\_THEN\ $f$\ (|-\ ?$x$.$t[x]$)} 
is a tactic that, given a goal, generates the subgoal 
obtained
by applying $f$ to \ml{($t[x]$|-$t[x]$)}.  The intuition is that if
\ml{|-\ ?$x$.$t[x]$} holds then \ml{|-\ $t[x]$} 
holds for some value of $x$ (as long as the
variable $x$ is not free elsewhere in the theorem or current goal).
%(The choice of the witness is `understood' by the justification function.)
This gives an easy way of using existentially quantified theorems,
something that is otherwise awkward.

The new method has other applications as well, including as an
implementation technique. 
For example,
\index{tactics!indirect implementation of}
taking \ml{DISJ\_CASES\_THEN} as basic, \ml{DISJ\_CASES\_TAC}
can be defined by:

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   let DISJ_CASES_TAC = DISJ_CASES_THEN ASSUME_TAC
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent Similarly, the method is useful for modifying existing tactics 
(\eg\ resolution tactics) without
having to re-program them in \ML.  This avoids the danger of
introducing tactics
whose justifications may fail,
\index{failure, of tactics} a particularly difficult problem to
track down; it is also much easier than starting from scratch.

The main theorem continuation functions in the system are:

\begin{hol}\begin{verbatim}
   ANTE_RES_THEN
   CHOOSE_THEN      X_CHOOSE_THEN
   CONJUNCTS_THEN   CONJUNCTS_THEN2
   DISJ_CASES_THEN  DISJ_CASES_THEN2   DISJ_CASES_THENL 
   DISCH_THEN
   IMP_RES_THEN
   RES_THEN
   STRIP_THM_THEN
   STRIP_GOAL_THEN
\end{verbatim}\end{hol}

\noindent See \REFERENCE\ for full details. For \ml{INDUCT\_THEN},

see Section~\ref{avrasi} and \REFERENCE.\index{tactics!for manipulating assumptions|)}