File: mpcref.tex

package info (click to toggle)
minlog 4.0.99.20080304-4
  • links: PTS
  • area: main
  • in suites: lenny
  • size: 5,596 kB
  • ctags: 3,597
  • sloc: lisp: 80,596; makefile: 250; sh: 11
file content (920 lines) | stat: -rw-r--r-- 31,990 bytes parent folder | download | duplicates (4)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
% $Id: mpcref.tex,v 1.12 2008/01/25 13:30:19 logik Exp $
\documentclass[11pt,a4paper]{article}

% for pdftex
\usepackage[backref]{hyperref}

% set all margins to 1 inch
\evensidemargin 0pt
\oddsidemargin 0pt
\textwidth \paperwidth
\addtolength\textwidth{-2in}

\topmargin 0pt
\addtolength\topmargin{-\headheight}
\addtolength\topmargin{-\headsep}
\topskip 0pt
\textheight \paperheight
\addtolength\textheight{-2in}

\parindent 0pt
\parskip .5\baselineskip plus .5\baselineskip

\def\MPC{\textsc{Mpc}}
\def\Minlog{\textsc{Minlog}}

\title{The \Minlog\ Proof Checker: \MPC}
\author{Martin Ruckert}


\begin{document}

\maketitle
\tableofcontents

\newpage

\section{Lexical Structure}
The input of \MPC\ is a stream of characters that usually comes from a regular text
file (see Invocation). \MPC\ will group these characters together to form 
whitespace, comments, punctuation, strings, names, keywords, numbers, or indices.
Keywords, punctuation, names, numbers and indices are collectively called tokens.

\paragraph{Whitespace:}
You will know whitespace, when you see it. Otherwise, you may look up
the function isspace in a scheme revised five report. Whatever this function
regards as whitespace, is whitespace.

Whitespace is of no
significance to \textsc{MPC}---except between a name and an index (see below).
Its only purpose is to separate two
tokens and to make files more readable.

\paragraph{Comments:} Comments are started with \verb\//\ and
extend until the end of line or the end of file. Like whitespace,
comments separate tokens and can improve readability.

\paragraph{Numbers and Indices}
Numbers and Indices are both formed from the digits 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, and
9. They form an index, if they follow immediately after a
name, or after an underscore \verb/_/, or after a caret \verb/^/.
Otherwise, they form a number.

\paragraph{Punctuation}
The following characters are punctuation:
\verb/{/,
\verb/}/,
\verb/[/,
\verb/]/,
\verb/(/,
\verb/)/,
\verb/./,
\verb/;/, 
\verb/,/,
and
\verb/"/.

\paragraph{Strings}
Strings start with a ``\verb/"/'' character and end with the following ``\verb/"/''
character or the end of the input. Inside a string any character can be
escaped by a preceding backslash ``\verb/\/''. The preceding backslash strips
a character of any special meaning and inserts it plainly into the string.
This is useful only for the characters that have any special
meaning: the quote and the backslash itself. That is, ``\verb/\"/'' will insert
a double-quote into the string without terminating it, and ``\verb/\\/'' will
insert a single backslash into the string. 


\paragraph{Names} Names are formed either from letters only or from
special characters only. All characters except whitespace, digits, letters, and
punctuation are considered special characters.
Names can be indexed by a number. There must be no
whitespace between name and index. E.g \verb/f15/ is the function
$f_{15}$ whereas \verb/f 15/ is the function $f$ applied to the
number $15$.

Examples of names are ``\verb/hello/'', ``\verb/sigma/'', ``\verb/==>/'', and ``\verb/|-/''.
The following strings are {\bf not} names: ``\verb/x_i/'', ``\verb/(;-)/'', 
or ``\verb/id3tag/''.

Note: All names of types,
variables, functions, or pre\-di\-cates must be declared before they
can be used.  Once an alphabetic name is declared, it provides an
infinite sequence of objects (types, variables, functions, predicates)
using indexing.

\paragraph{Keywords} Keywords are predefined names with a fixed, build in meaning.
All the keywords that \MPC\ knows about are explained below.


\section{Syntax}
The syntax of \MPC\ uses as main ingredients formulas and terms. 
Since \MPC\ is a front-end to the \Minlog\ system it uses the \Minlog\ syntax
to specify formulas and terms. To find out how to
write formulas and terms you can either rely on your intuition or consult the 
\Minlog\ manual. Here we describe only the syntax that is particular to \MPC.


\MPC\ is designed to process normal text files.
Every text file starts with the keyword
``\texttt{MPC}'' followed by a semicolon ``\texttt{;}''.
Then a list of commands follows. 

\subsection{Commands}
A command can be one of the following:
\begin{itemize}
\item \texttt{LOAD} \texttt{"}\textit{Filename}\texttt{"} \texttt{;}\\
   reads in the given file as \textsc{Scheme} code.  Every possible effect
   can be obtained in this way by writing appropriate \textsc{Scheme} code.

   If the file does not exist in the current directory, it is searched
   for in a directory of library files.

\item \texttt{INCLUDE} \texttt{"}\textit{Filename}\texttt{"} \texttt{;}\\
   reads in the given file as \MPC\ code. 
   It can be used to store e.g.\ a collection of definitions
   and axioms in a file and load them into several proofs.

   If the file does not exist in the current directory, it is searched
   for in a directory of library files. Currently two libraries exist:
   nat.mpc gives definitions of natural numbers, and list.mpc gives
   definitions for lists.

\item \texttt{SCHEME} \texttt{"}\textit{Scheme Expression}\texttt{";}\\ 
   reads the given string with the \textsc{Scheme} function
   \texttt{read} and supplies the result as an argument to the
   \textsc{Scheme} function \texttt{eval}, in effect evaluating the
   given string like regular \textsc{Scheme} code.  Note that inside a
   string doublequotes need to be escaped by a preceding
   backslash. For example:

   \verb/SCHEME "(display \"hello world!\")";/.


\item \texttt{PROOF;}
   starts a proof. This will set the list of known facts to 
   an empty list. \MPC\ will forget all previously proved formulas.

   Two variations exist: \texttt{CLASSIC PROOF} starts a proof with the
   rule of Stability enabled---that is you can conclude $A$ from $\lnot\lnot A$.
   
     \texttt{INTUITIONISTIC PROOF} starts a proof with the special
   rule of Ex-Falso-Quodlibet enabled --- that is you can conclude any $A$ from
$\bot$. 
    

\item \texttt{END;}
  terminates a proof (currently optional).


\item A declaration, 
\item an assumption, 
\item a claim, 
\item a block, or
\item a syntax specification as detailed below.
\end{itemize}


\subsection{Declarations}
Declarations are used to tell \MPC\ about types, variables,
functions, and predicates.

\paragraph{Types:}
Types come as type variables, as simultaneously defined finite algebras,
or as composed types. Only variable types and algebra types need
to be declared. Type operators (mostly \verb/=>/) can be freely 
used to construct composed types. 

To declare a type variable the keyword ``\texttt{TYPE}'' is followed
by a dot ``\texttt{.}'', a list of names, and finally a semicolon
``\texttt{;}''.  It will make the given names type variables. For
example:

\texttt{TYPE . rho sigma tau;}

will make \texttt{rho}, \texttt{sigma}, and \texttt{tau} new type variables.

There is one predefined type variable \texttt{alpha} that exists, for
internal reasons, right from the start.

By adding an index to a variable name, an infinite number of different
type variables can be obtained, e.g.\ \texttt{alpha5},
\texttt{tau123}, or \texttt{sigma1}.

Algebra types are described in the next section.

\paragraph{Algebra Types:}

Objects of a free algebra type are build by applying an appropriate
constructor to already existing objects.  For example, the free
algebra of natural numbers can be defined with the constructors
\texttt{zero} and \texttt{successor}.

\texttt{zero} is a constructor of empty arity, that is, it is applied to 
no object and yields a natural number, and \texttt{successor}
is applied to a natural number and yields again a natural number.
Hence ``\texttt{successor zero}'' is for example a natural number.

To specify an algebra, the name of the algebra together with the name
of the constructors and their arity has to be given.  The syntax is:

\noindent
\texttt{ALGEBRA} \textit{algebra-name} \verb/{/ \verb/{/ \verb/{/\\
\texttt{\ \  \textit{constructor-type} . \textit{constructor-name} ; }\\ 
\texttt{\ \  \textit{constructor-type} . \textit{constructor-name} ; }\\ 
\ldots\\
\ \verb/}/\ \texttt{;}

For example to define the algebra of natural numbers, one can write

\noindent
\texttt{ALGEBRA nat}\ \verb/{/\\
\texttt{\ \ nat . zero ;} \\
\texttt{\ \ nat => nat . successor ;} \\
\ \verb/}/

Algebras can have type parameters.  For example a list type, might
have the type of the list elements as a parameter.  To declare an
algebra with type parameters, the number of type parameters has to be
given after the algebra name.  In this case the type variables
\texttt{alpha0}, \texttt{alpha1}, \ldots can be used in the
\textit{constructor-types}.

For example to define the free algebra of lists of elements of type
\texttt{alpha0} one can write:

\noindent
\texttt{ALGEBRA list 1}\ \verb/{/\\
\texttt{\ \ list . nil ;} \\
\texttt{\ \ alpha0 => list => list . cons ;} \\
\ \verb/}/\ \texttt{;}

Finally, several algebras can be defined simultaneously
by listing all their names after the keyword \texttt{ALGEBRA}.

As a last example we construct an algebra of labeled trees, where labels
can be either of type \texttt{alpha0}, or of type \texttt{alpha1}, or
again labeled trees.

\noindent
\texttt{ALGEBRA tree label 2}\ \verb/{/\\
\texttt{alpha0 => label . first ;}\\
\texttt{alpha1 => label . second ;}\\
\texttt{tree => label . third ;}

\noindent
\texttt{tree . empty;}\\
\texttt{label => tree => tree => tree . node ;}\\
\ \verb/}/\ \texttt{;}

\paragraph{Variables:}
Variables are declared by specifying their type. The syntax is:

\noindent
\textit{type} \texttt{.} \textit{variablenames} \texttt{;}

For example

\noindent
\texttt{nat => nat . f g ; }

defines \texttt{f} and \texttt{g} as function variables
mapping natural numbers to natural numbers. Similarly \texttt{f3} or
\texttt{g2} are such function variables.

\paragraph{Functions:}

Function constants have a name and a type (like function variables)
but in addition have fixed computational rules or rewrite rules
attached to them. These rules are used automatically by the prover
to find out whether two terms are equal.

A function declaration starts with the keyword \texttt{FUNCTION}
followed by the target type of the function, a dot, the name of the
function and a list of argument types.  After the name follows a list
of rules enclosed in braces. A semicolon terminates the function
declaration. As a special convenience, syntax declarations (see below)
can be used inside the rule list.

A rule has the form \textit{term} \texttt{->} \textit{term} \texttt{;}
It states that the left term can be replaced by the right term.  Of
course, the principal operator of the left term has to be the function
currently being defined.  Furthermore each rule must have a unique
left hand side.  More rules can be added if prefixed with the keyword
\texttt{REWRITE}.  These additional rules are applied more carefully
(avoiding rewrite loops) and hence are more flexible but slower.

The following example illustrates this:

\begin{tabbing}
\tt SYNTAX ++ PREFIXOP successor ; \\
\tt FUNCTION nat . plus (nat nat) \\
\tt \verb/{/ \= \\
\>\tt  SYNTAX + ADDOP plus ;\\
\\
\>\tt  \phantom{REWRITE} n + zero -> n ;\\
\>\tt  \phantom{REWRITE}        n + ++m ->  ++(n + m) ;\\
\>\tt  REWRITE zero + n -> n;\\
\>\tt  REWRITE ++n + m -> ++(n +  m) ;\\
\>\tt  REWRITE n + ( m+  k) -> (n +  m) + k ;   \\
\tt \verb/}/;\\
\end{tabbing}

Note, that syntax declarations, explained below, are allowed inside
a function declaration to enable the use of a more convenient
syntax, e.g.\ infix notation, if so desired.

Functions, by default, are total functions.  It is possible to define
partial functions by adding the keyword \texttt{PARTIAL} in front of
the keyword \texttt{FUNCTION}.

\paragraph{Predicates:}

To declare a predicate the keyword \texttt{PRED} is used followed by a
list of types of the arguments (if any), a dot, a list of predicate
names, and finally a semicolon.

For example:

\noindent
\texttt{PRED . A B ; }

defines two predicate variables \texttt{A} and \texttt{B} (as well as
\texttt{A0}, \texttt{A1}, \ldots).  They take no arguments and can be
used like propositional variables.

\noindent
\texttt{PRED nat nat . R ; }

defines a binary predicate over natural numbers (a relation), and

\noindent
\texttt{PRED nat=>nat . P ; }
defines a unary predicate over functions of natural numbers.


\subsection{Assumptions and Claims}
An assumption is a formula followed by a dot ``\texttt{.}'' and a
claim is a formula followed by a semicolon ``\texttt{;}''.  In the
first case the formula is added to the list of known formulas, in the
second case an attempt is made to prove the formula form the formulas
already known to be true.

Formulas are defined inductively: Every predicate variable \texttt{A}
is a formula.  If \texttt{M} and \texttt{N} are formulas then
\texttt{M \& N} (conjunction) and \texttt{M -> N} (implication) are
formulas.  If \texttt{M} is a formula and \texttt{x} is a variable,
then \texttt{all x M} and \texttt{ex x M} are formulas.

Examples of formulas and details of how proofs work can be found
below.

For example:

\noindent
\texttt{PRED . A ; // A is a proposition }\\
\texttt{A. // we assume A holds }\\
\texttt{A \& A; // we claim that A \& A can be proven}

\subsection{Blocks}
Blocks are used to construct conditional proofs.

They start with \verb\{\ and end with \verb\}\.
After the opening brace follows either a formula or a variable
followed by a dot. This is the local formula or variable of 
this block.

Next a block contains a non empty sequence of claims or other blocks.

When the block is closed it proves an implication --- in case of a
local formula --- or an all quantified formula --- in case of a local
variable.  The exact usage is explained below.  Here an example may
suffice:

\begin{tabbing}
\tt PRED alpha . P ; // P is a predicate \\
\tt alpha . x ; // x is a variable of type alpha \\
\tt \verb/{/ \=\tt x0 . // assume x0 is given \\
\tt \>\tt \verb/{/ \= \tt P x0 . // assume further that P of x0 holds  \\
\tt \> \>\tt P x0 ; // then P of x0 holds  \\
\tt \>\tt \verb/}/ // this proves P x0 -> P x0  \\
\tt \verb/}/ // this proves all x0 . P x0 -> P x0  \\
\end{tabbing}


\subsection{Syntax Declarations}
In mathematics, functions are often written in infix, prefix, or
postfix notation.  Instead of writing \texttt{plus x y} --- the
function \texttt{plus} applied to \texttt{x} and \texttt{y} --- we
like to write \texttt{x + y}.  To facilitate this \MPC\ has
syntax declarations.

A syntax declaration starts with the keyword \texttt{SYNTAX} followed
by the name of the new operator, followed by the tokentype, followed
by a term, and a semicolon.

A tokentype is one of the following (in order of increasing 
binding strength):
     \texttt{PAIROP},
     \texttt{IMPOP},
     \texttt{OROP}, 
     \texttt{ANDOP},
     \texttt{RELOP},
     \texttt{ADDOP},
     \texttt{MULOP},
     \texttt{PREFIXOP}, 
     \texttt{POSTFIXOP}, or
     \texttt{CONST}.
A \texttt{PAIROP} and \texttt{IMPOP} are right associative,
a \texttt{RELOP} is not associative, and all other infix operators are
left associative.

After the syntax declaration, any term containing the new operator as
main connective is replaced by the term given in the syntax
declaration applied to the arguments of the operator.

For example:
 
\noindent
\texttt{boole . a b; // a and b are booleans. }\\
\texttt{boole=>boole=>boole . f ; // f is a function. }\\
\texttt{SYNTAX | ADDOP f0 ; // we write | as infix operator for f0.}

\noindent
\texttt{all a . true|a . // for all a ((f0 true) a) holds.}\\
\texttt{all a,b . a|b -> b|a. //  f0 is commutative.}\\
\texttt{false|false -> bot. // ((f0 false) false) implies bot.}


Syntax declarations might be parameterized with type variables 
\texttt{alpha0}, \texttt{alpha1}, \ldots If the defining term contains
one of these type variables, the types of the actual arguments are matched
against the type of the operator to instantiate the type variables.
If the types match, the syntax declaration is used. 

Further, the same operator might be redefined in several syntax declarations
as long as all of these declarations use the same tokentype. Multiple
declarations are tested in the order declared and the first matching declaration is
used.


Note: Syntax declarations are allowed inside a function declaration.




\section{Proofs}

The \Minlog\ Proof Checker is able to check proofs in ``natural
deduction'' style.

It maintains a list of formulas, called the context, which are assumed
or known or proven to be true.  Initially this list is empty; using
the keyword \texttt{PROOF;} it can be reset to an empty list at any
time to start a new proof.

There are only two methods to add a formula to the context: First, one
can assume the formula by just stating it and putting a dot behind it.
This is called an assumption. Example:

\begin{verbatim}
PRED . A B; // A and B are propositional variables
A. // Let's assume A holds
A -> B. // Let's assume A implies B
\end{verbatim}

Second, one can prove a formula from other formulas already known ---
i.e.\ fformulas already part of the context --- using the rules of
natural deduction.  The claim that a formula can be proved is
expressed by stating the formula followed by semicolon.  This is
called a claim.  \MPC\ then will check whether there are indeed
formulas in the context, which prove the new formula using exactly one
rule of natural deduction.

If that is not possible, \MPC\ will start a limited proof
search trying to obtain a more complicated proof of the claimed
formula.  If a proof is found this is indicated in an appropriate
warning message. It tells the user that the formula is indeed
provable, but not with a single step.

If the proof search does not discover a proof, \MPC\ will
simply assume the formula and continue.  It will output a
corresponding error message, and it should be clear that the proof has
still a gap at this point.

Whenever a formula is added to the context, it receives a unique
number and \MPC\ will use this number later to refer to this
formula in its output.

A typical proof will first define the necessary types, variables,
functions and predicates to establish the language of the theory, then
it states a list of assumptions made (these are the axioms of the
theory) and finally it starts to make claims, adding one formula at a
time to the pool of knowledge (the context) available for the theory.
In the end it will conclude with the final formula, a theorem of the
theory.

Often the language of the theory and its axioms are put into include
files, to be able to conveniently load them before starting a proof.

In the following sections, we will discuss all the proof rules of
natural deduction, one at a time.

\subsection{Simple Rules}
To be applicable, these rules just require certain formulas to be
already in the context.

\paragraph{Trivial Proofs}
If a formula, after normalization, is the same as a formula 
in the context, it is proven by identity. Likewise,
if a formula, by normalization, reduces to \texttt{True}, it is
proven.



\paragraph{And Elimination:}
If a formula of the form $A \land B$ is in the context,
it is possible to derive either $A$ or $B$ in one step.
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
A & B. // 0 assumed.
A; // OK, 1 proved by and-elim-left from 0
B; // OK, 2 proved by and-elim-right from 0
\end{verbatim}


\paragraph{And Introduction:}
If two formulas $A$ and $B$ are part of the context,
it is possible to derive $A \land B$ in one step.
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
A. // 0 assumed.
B. // 1 assumed.
A & B; // OK, 2 proved by and-intro from 0 and 1
\end{verbatim}

\paragraph{Implication Elimination:}
If an implication $A \to B$ and its condition $A$
are part of the context,
it is possible to derive the conclusion $B$ in one step.
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
A -> B. // 0 assumed.
A. // 1 assumed.
B; // OK, 2 proved by imp-elim from 0 and 1
\end{verbatim}

\paragraph{All Elimination:}
If an all formula $\forall x\, A x$ 
is part of the context,
it is possible to derive the conclusion $A t$ 
for any term $t$ of the appropriate type in one step.
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
all x A x. // 0 assumed.
A t; // OK, 1 proved by all-elim from 0 using t
\end{verbatim}

\paragraph{Existential Introduction:}
If a formula $A t$ for some term $t$ is part of the context,
it is possible to derive $\exists x\, A x$ in one step,
where $x$ is a variable of the same type as $t$.
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
A t. // 0 assumed.
ex x A x; // OK, 1 proved by ex-intro from 0 using t
\end{verbatim}

\subsection{Block Rules}
Sometimes it is necessary in a proof to temporarily make an assumption
only to discard it later again.  For example, for proving an
implication $A \to B$, one would first assume $A$ holds, and then
prove $B$ under this assumption.  Once this is done, one can conclude
that $A \to B$, and this does no longer depend on the assumption $A$.

The assumption $A$ in this example behaves like a local assumption
with a limited scope.  In programming languages, the usual way to
introduce objects with limited scope is a block structure.  In
\textsc{MPC}, blocks are enclosed in curly braces and introduce
exactly one local object, either a formula or a variable.  The scope
of this local object is its defining block and all blocks nested
inside it.

\paragraph{Implication Introduction:}
As said before, an implication $A \to B$ is proved by assuming $A$ and
then proving $B$ under this assumption.  Once this is done, one can
conclude that $A \to B$.  In \textsc{MPC}, one opens a block with the
local assumption $A$ and proves inside this block the formula $B$.
Immediately after the formula $B$ the block is closed again.  After
the closing brace of the block, \MPC\ will discard all the
formulas added to the context during the block (since these may depend
on the assumption $A$) and adds the implication $A \to B$ to the
context, $A$ being the local formula of the block and $B$ the last
formula of the block.

Example:
\begin{verbatim}
{ A t. // 0 assumed.
  ex x A x; // OK, 1 proved by ex-intro from 0 using t
} OK, 2 A t -> ex x A x proved.
ex x A x; // ERROR: 3 assumed.  Proof not found.
\end{verbatim} 


\paragraph{All Introduction:}
The proof of a formula with an outer universal quantifier is similar
to the proof of an implication: Under the assumption that some $x$ is
given, one proves $A x$.  This is sufficient to conclude $\forall x\,
Ax$.

For \textsc{MPC}, the proof consists of a block with a local variable
$x$ with the last formula being $A x$.  At the end of the block,
\MPC\ will discard all the formulas added to the context during
the block and adds the formula $\forall x\, Ax$ to the context.

Example:
\begin{verbatim}
{ x. // x assumed.
  { A x. // 0 assumed.
    A x; // OK, 1 proved by 0
  } OK, 2 A x -> A x proved.
} OK, 3 all x.A x -> A x proved.
\end{verbatim} 

\paragraph{Existential Elimination:}
A proof of a formula $B$ may use an existentially quantified formula
$\exists x\, Ax$.  It typically proceeds like this: If we know that
$\exists x\, Ax$, let us assume we have such an $x$, call it $x_0$,
such that $A x_0$ holds,\ldots and from this the proof continues to
prove the formula B.  This then constitutes a proof of $B$ from
$\exists x\, Ax$ under the side condition that the $x_0$ is not a free
variable of $B$.

This proof can be formulated for \MPC\ in exactly the same
fashion as outlined above using two nested blocks.  The first block
introduces the local variable $x_0$ and the second block the local
assumption $A x_0$.  Once the formula $B$ is proved from this, both
blocks are closed.  This in effect proves the formula $\forall x. Ax
\to B$.  This, together with the formula $\exists x\, Ax$, can be used
to finally prove $B$ using the rule of existential elimination.
 
Example:
\begin{verbatim}
ex x.A x & B. // 0 assumed.
{ x0. // x0 assumed.
  { A x0 & B. // 1 assumed.
    B; // OK, 2 proved by and-elim-right from 1
  } OK, 3 A x0 & B -> B proved.
} OK, 4 all x0.A x0 & B -> B proved.
B; // OK, 5 proved by ex-elim from 4 and 0
\end{verbatim} 


\subsection{Induction}
Induction is used to prove that a formula $Ax$ holds for all objects
$x$ of a given algebra type $\tau$.  This is done by considering all
constructors $C_1,\ldots,C_n$ of the algebra that are capable of
producing an object of the type in question and proving for each one
of them that the formula $A C_i \ldots$ holds provided that the
formula holds already for all arguments of $C_i$ of type $\tau$.  Once
this is done, all these formulas together, prove by the principle of
induction, that $\forall x\, Ax$.

We illustrate this using the standard example of natural numbers.

The free algebra of natural numbers \texttt{nat} is generated
from two constructors: \texttt{Zero} of type \texttt{nat}
and \texttt{Succ} of type $\texttt{nat}\to\texttt{nat}$.
For convenience we write \texttt{0} for \texttt{Zero} and
$\mathtt{++}n$ for $\texttt{Succ}\,n$

To prove $\forall n\, An$ by induction, we need to prove first $A
\mathtt{0}$ and $\forall n\, An \to A \mathtt{++} n$, then we can
conclude the desired result.  For example lets prove that $\forall n
\exists m \, m = n+1$.  We proceed like this:

First $1 = \mathtt{0}+1$ and therefore $\exists m\, m=\mathtt{0}+1$.

Second, assume $n$ is given and $\exists m\, m = n + 1$ holds.
Then there is an $m_0$ with $m_0 = n + 1$, and thus
$m_0 +1 = \mathtt{++}n +1$.  By existential introduction,
we conclude $\exists m\, m= \mathtt{++}n + 1$ and
have proved $\forall n\, (\exists m\, m = n + 1 \to
\exists m\, m= \mathtt{++}n + 1)$.

From these, by induction, we infer: $\forall n \exists m \, m = n+1$.

The complete proof written for \MPC\ reads:
\begin{verbatim}
MPC;

INCLUDE "nat.mpc";

PROOF;                 // initializing mpc1
1=0+1;                 // OK, 0 proved trivial
ex m m=0+1;            // OK, 1 proved by ex-intro from 0 using 1
{ n.                   // n assumed.
  { ex m m=n+1.        // 2 assumed.
    { m0.              // m0 assumed.
      { m0=n+1.        // 3 assumed.
        m0+1= ++n+1;   // OK, 4 proved by 3
        ex m m= ++n+1; // OK, 5 proved by ex-intro from 4 using m0+1
      }                // OK, 6 m0=n+1 -> ex m m= ++n+1 proved.
    }                  // OK, 7 all m0.m0=n+1 -> ex m m= ++n+1 proved.
    ex m m= ++n+1;     // OK, 8 proved by ex-elim from 7 and 2
  }                    // OK, 9 ex m m=n+1 -> ex m m= ++n+1 proved.
}                      // OK, 10 all n.ex m m=n+1 -> ex m m= ++n+1 proved.
all n ex m m=n+1;      // OK, 11 proved by ind from 10 1
\end{verbatim}


\subsection{Proof by Cases}
Proof by cases is similar to induction but weaker. Again, we prove
that a proposition $Ax$ holds for all objects
$x$ of a given algebra type $\tau$.  This is done by considering all
constructors $C_1,\ldots,C_n$ of the algebra that are capable of
producing an object of the type in question and proving for each one
of them that the formula $A C_i \ldots$ holds.
In contrast to the rule of induction however, no induction hypothesis
is available in the proof.

A special case is the proof by cases for objects of type \texttt{boole}.
Here, the constructors are \texttt{True} and \texttt{False}. We prove
$Ax$ by considering the two cases, proving $A\texttt{True}$ and
$A\texttt{False}$ to conclude $\forall x\, Ax$. Typically, this
formula is then applied to the boolean term $t$ in question
to obtaining $At$. 
Since this process is quite common, in addition to the usual proof by cases
rule, an equivalent and more convenient
rule is built into  \MPC: the proof by boolean cases.
To prove any formula $A$, you just have to prove $t \rightarrow A$ and
$(\lnot t) \rightarrow A$.




\subsection{Intuitionistic and Classical Logic}
\MPC\ provides two keywords \texttt{CLASSIC} and
\texttt{INTUITIONISTIC} to activate proof rules for classic and
intuitionistic logic, respectively.  If a proof starts with
``\texttt{INTUITIONISTIC PROOF;}'', the proof rule ``ex falso
quodlibet'' is enabled.  It allows to conclude from \texttt{bot} any
formula whatsoever.  If a proof starts with ``\texttt{CLASSIC
PROOF;}'' in addition the stronger proof rule of ``stability'' is
enabled.  It allows to conclude the formula $A$ from a statement of
$\lnot \lnot A$.  It is an easy exercise to prove $\bot \to A$ from
$\lnot \lnot A \to A$, and therefore stability alone would be
sufficient to have classical logic.  It is however convenient to have
``ex falso quodlibet'' in addition.  This weaker rule is always tested
first.

As an example, we present a proof of the Pierce Formula
$((P\rightarrow Q) \rightarrow P) \rightarrow P$.

\begin{verbatim}
CLASSIC PROOF;
PRED . P Q;

{ (P -> Q) -> P.     // 0 assumed.
  { P -> bot.        // 1 assumed.
    { P.             // 2 assumed.
      bot;           // OK, 3 proved by imp-elim from 1 and 2
      Q;             // OK, 4 proved by EFQ from 3
    }                // OK, 5 P -> Q proved.
    P -> Q;          // OK, 6 proved by 5
    P;               // OK, 7 proved by imp-elim from 0 and 6
    bot;             // OK, 8 proved by imp-elim from 1 and 7
  }                  // OK, 9 (P -> bot) -> bot proved.
  (P -> bot) -> bot; // OK, 10 proved by 9
  P;                 // OK, 11 proved by Stability from 10
}                    // OK, 12 ((P -> Q) -> P) -> P proved.
END; 
\end{verbatim}

\newpage
\appendix

\section{Library code}
This \MPC\ code may serve as an example to illustrate
the concepts of \MPC.

\subsection{Natural Numbers}

\begin{verbatim}
MPC;

ALGEBRA nat  0
{ nat=>nat   . Succ ;
  nat  . Zero  ;
};

nat . n m k;

// to use numbers we have to provide scheme code
// converting numbers to terms using internals of Minlog
SCHEME 
"(define (make-numeric-term n)
  (if (= n 0)
      (pt \"Zero\")
      (make-term-in-app-form
       (pt \"Succ\")
       (make-numeric-term (- n 1)))))" ;

SCHEME
"(define (is-numeric-term? term)
  (or
   (and (term-in-const-form? term)
	(string=? \"Zero\" 
	         (const-to-name 
		   (term-in-const-form-to-const term))))
   (and (term-in-app-form? term)
	(let ((op (term-in-app-form-to-op term)))
	  (and (term-in-const-form? op)
	       (string=? \"Succ\" 
	                (const-to-name 
			  (term-in-const-form-to-const op)))
	       (is-numeric-term? 
	         (term-in-app-form-to-arg term)))))))";

SCHEME
"(define (numeric-term-to-number term)
  (if (equal? term (pt \"Zero\"))
      0
      (+ 1 (numeric-term-to-number 
             (term-in-app-form-to-arg term)))))";


SYNTAX ++ PREFIXOP Succ;

FUNCTION nat . Plus(nat nat)
{ SYNTAX + ADDOP Plus;

          n + 0       -> n;
          n + ++m     -> ++(n + m);
  REWRITE 0 + n       -> n;
  REWRITE ++n + m     -> ++(n + m);
  REWRITE n + (m + k) -> n + m + k;   
};


FUNCTION nat . Times(nat nat)
{ SYNTAX * MULOP Times;
          n * 0       -> 0;
          n * ++m     -> (n*m)+n;
  REWRITE 0*n         -> 0;
  REWRITE ++n*m       -> (n*m)+m;
  REWRITE n * (m * k) -> n * m * k;
};

FUNCTION boole . Less(nat nat)
{ SYNTAX < RELOP Less;
  n < 0     -> False;
  0 < ++n   -> True;
  ++n < ++m -> n<m;    
};
\end{verbatim}


\newpage
\subsection{Polymorphic Lists}
\begin{verbatim}
MPC;

ALGEBRA list 1 {
list                   . Nil;
alpha1 => list => list . Cons ;
};

// a generic variable of type (list alpha)
(list alpha) . l;

SYNTAX :: PAIROP    (Cons alpha);
SYNTAX :  POSTFIXOP [alpha] alpha ::(Nil alpha);
// example x :: y :: z :


FUNCTION list alpha => list alpha . ListAppend (list alpha) 
{ SYNTAX :+: PAIROP (ListAppend alpha);
  (ListAppend alpha)(Nil alpha)   -> [l_2]l_2;
  (ListAppend alpha)(alpha :: l1) -> [l2] alpha::(l1:+:l2);
};


INCLUDE "nat.mpc";

FUNCTION nat . ListLength(list alpha)
{ SYNTAX  lh PREFIXOP (ListLength alpha); 
          lh (Nil alpha)  -> 0 ;
          lh (alpha :: l) -> ++ lh l;
  REWRITE lh (l1 :+: l2)  -> lh l1 + lh l2;
};
\end{verbatim}

\end{document}


  
%%% Local Variables: 
%%% mode: latex-math
%%% End: