1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 732 733 734 735 736 737 738 739 740 741 742 743 744 745 746 747 748 749 750 751 752 753 754 755 756 757 758 759 760 761 762 763 764 765 766 767 768 769 770 771 772 773 774 775 776 777 778 779 780 781 782 783 784 785 786 787 788 789 790 791 792 793 794 795 796 797 798 799 800 801 802 803 804 805 806 807 808 809 810 811 812 813 814 815 816 817 818 819 820 821 822 823 824 825 826 827 828 829 830 831 832 833 834 835 836 837 838 839 840 841 842 843 844 845 846 847 848 849 850 851 852 853 854 855 856 857 858 859 860 861 862 863 864 865 866 867 868 869 870 871 872 873 874 875 876 877 878 879 880 881 882 883 884 885 886 887 888 889 890 891 892 893 894 895 896 897 898 899 900 901 902 903 904 905 906 907 908 909 910 911 912 913 914 915 916 917 918 919 920 921 922 923 924 925 926 927 928 929 930 931 932 933 934 935 936 937 938 939 940 941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 949 950 951 952 953 954 955 956 957 958 959 960 961 962 963 964 965 966 967 968 969 970 971 972 973 974 975 976 977 978 979 980 981 982 983 984 985 986 987 988 989 990 991 992 993 994 995 996 997 998 999 1000 1001 1002 1003 1004 1005 1006 1007 1008 1009 1010 1011 1012 1013 1014 1015 1016 1017 1018 1019 1020 1021 1022 1023 1024 1025 1026 1027 1028 1029 1030 1031 1032 1033 1034 1035 1036 1037 1038 1039 1040 1041 1042 1043 1044 1045 1046 1047 1048 1049 1050 1051 1052 1053 1054 1055 1056 1057 1058 1059 1060 1061 1062 1063 1064 1065 1066 1067 1068 1069 1070 1071 1072 1073 1074 1075 1076 1077 1078 1079 1080 1081 1082 1083 1084 1085 1086 1087 1088 1089 1090 1091 1092 1093 1094 1095 1096 1097 1098 1099 1100 1101 1102 1103 1104 1105 1106 1107 1108 1109 1110 1111 1112 1113 1114 1115 1116 1117 1118 1119 1120 1121 1122 1123 1124 1125 1126 1127 1128 1129 1130 1131 1132 1133 1134 1135 1136 1137 1138 1139 1140 1141 1142 1143 1144 1145 1146 1147 1148 1149 1150 1151 1152 1153 1154 1155 1156 1157 1158 1159 1160 1161 1162 1163 1164 1165 1166 1167 1168 1169 1170 1171 1172 1173 1174 1175 1176 1177 1178 1179 1180 1181 1182 1183 1184 1185 1186 1187 1188 1189 1190 1191 1192 1193 1194 1195 1196 1197 1198 1199 1200 1201 1202 1203 1204 1205 1206 1207 1208 1209 1210 1211 1212 1213 1214 1215 1216 1217 1218 1219 1220 1221 1222 1223 1224 1225 1226 1227 1228 1229 1230 1231 1232 1233 1234 1235 1236 1237 1238 1239 1240 1241 1242 1243 1244 1245 1246 1247 1248 1249 1250 1251 1252 1253 1254 1255 1256 1257 1258 1259 1260 1261 1262 1263 1264 1265 1266 1267 1268 1269 1270 1271 1272 1273 1274 1275 1276 1277 1278 1279 1280 1281 1282 1283 1284 1285 1286 1287 1288 1289 1290 1291 1292 1293 1294 1295 1296 1297 1298 1299 1300 1301 1302 1303 1304 1305 1306 1307 1308 1309 1310 1311 1312 1313 1314 1315 1316 1317 1318 1319 1320 1321 1322 1323 1324 1325 1326 1327 1328 1329 1330 1331 1332 1333 1334 1335 1336 1337 1338 1339 1340 1341 1342 1343 1344 1345 1346 1347 1348 1349 1350 1351 1352 1353 1354 1355 1356 1357 1358 1359 1360 1361 1362 1363 1364 1365 1366 1367 1368 1369 1370 1371 1372 1373 1374 1375 1376 1377 1378 1379 1380 1381 1382 1383 1384 1385 1386 1387 1388 1389 1390 1391 1392 1393 1394 1395 1396 1397 1398 1399 1400 1401 1402 1403 1404 1405 1406 1407 1408 1409 1410 1411 1412 1413 1414 1415 1416 1417 1418 1419 1420 1421 1422 1423 1424 1425 1426 1427 1428 1429 1430 1431 1432 1433 1434 1435 1436 1437 1438 1439 1440 1441 1442 1443 1444 1445 1446 1447 1448 1449 1450 1451 1452 1453 1454 1455 1456 1457 1458 1459 1460 1461 1462 1463 1464 1465 1466 1467 1468 1469 1470 1471 1472 1473 1474 1475 1476 1477 1478 1479 1480 1481 1482 1483 1484 1485 1486 1487 1488 1489 1490 1491 1492 1493 1494 1495 1496 1497 1498 1499 1500 1501 1502 1503 1504 1505 1506 1507 1508 1509 1510 1511 1512 1513 1514 1515 1516 1517 1518 1519 1520 1521 1522 1523 1524 1525 1526 1527 1528 1529 1530 1531 1532 1533 1534 1535 1536 1537 1538 1539 1540 1541 1542 1543 1544 1545 1546 1547 1548 1549 1550 1551 1552 1553 1554 1555 1556 1557 1558 1559 1560 1561 1562 1563 1564 1565 1566 1567 1568 1569 1570 1571 1572 1573 1574 1575 1576 1577 1578 1579 1580 1581 1582 1583 1584 1585 1586 1587 1588 1589 1590 1591 1592 1593 1594 1595 1596 1597 1598 1599 1600 1601 1602 1603 1604 1605 1606 1607 1608 1609 1610 1611 1612 1613 1614 1615 1616 1617 1618 1619 1620 1621 1622 1623 1624 1625 1626 1627 1628 1629 1630 1631 1632 1633 1634 1635 1636 1637 1638 1639 1640 1641 1642 1643 1644 1645 1646 1647 1648 1649 1650 1651 1652 1653 1654 1655 1656 1657 1658 1659 1660 1661 1662 1663 1664 1665 1666 1667 1668 1669 1670 1671 1672 1673 1674 1675 1676 1677 1678 1679 1680 1681 1682 1683 1684 1685 1686 1687 1688 1689 1690 1691 1692 1693 1694 1695 1696 1697 1698 1699 1700 1701 1702 1703 1704 1705 1706 1707 1708 1709 1710 1711 1712 1713 1714 1715 1716 1717 1718 1719 1720 1721 1722 1723 1724 1725 1726 1727 1728 1729 1730 1731 1732 1733 1734 1735 1736 1737 1738 1739 1740 1741 1742 1743 1744 1745 1746 1747 1748 1749 1750 1751 1752 1753 1754 1755 1756 1757 1758 1759 1760 1761 1762 1763 1764 1765 1766 1767 1768 1769 1770 1771 1772 1773 1774 1775 1776 1777 1778 1779 1780 1781 1782 1783 1784 1785 1786 1787 1788 1789 1790 1791 1792 1793 1794 1795 1796 1797 1798 1799 1800 1801 1802 1803 1804 1805 1806 1807 1808 1809 1810 1811 1812 1813 1814 1815 1816 1817 1818 1819 1820 1821 1822 1823 1824 1825 1826 1827 1828 1829 1830 1831 1832 1833 1834 1835 1836 1837 1838 1839 1840 1841 1842 1843 1844 1845 1846 1847 1848 1849 1850 1851 1852 1853 1854 1855 1856 1857 1858 1859 1860 1861 1862 1863 1864 1865 1866 1867 1868 1869 1870 1871 1872 1873 1874 1875 1876 1877 1878 1879 1880 1881 1882 1883 1884 1885 1886 1887 1888 1889 1890 1891 1892 1893 1894 1895 1896 1897 1898 1899 1900 1901 1902 1903 1904 1905 1906 1907 1908 1909 1910 1911 1912 1913 1914 1915 1916 1917 1918 1919 1920 1921
|
\documentclass[../generics]{subfiles}
\begin{document}
\chapter{Completion}\label{completion}
\IndexDefinition{Knuth-Bendix algorithm}%
\index{completion!z@\igobble|seealso{Knuth-Bendix algorithm}}
\lettrine{K}{nuth-Bendix completion} is the central algorithm in the Requirement Machine. Completion attempts to construct a \index{convergent rewrite system}convergent rewrite system from a list of rewrite rules, and a convergent rewrite system allows us to decide if two terms have the same reduced form in a finite number of steps, solving the word problem. As we saw in the previous chapter, our initial rewrite rules are defined by the explicit requirements of a generic signature and its protocol dependencies. A desirable property of this mapping was given by Theorem~\ref{derivation to path}: a \emph{derived} requirement defines a rewrite path over these rewrite rules representing explicit requirements. All of this means that completion gives us a \emph{decision procedure} for the \index{derived requirement}derived requirements formalism: the question of whether any given derived requirement is satisfied---that is, if there exists a valid derivation built from explicit requirements---is easily solved by term reduction in a convergent rewrite system. This is the foundation on which we build both \index{generic signature query}generic signature queries and \index{requirement minimization}minimization.
\paragraph{The algorithm.} We'll give a self-contained description first, with much of the rest of the chapter devoted to examples. Our description can be supplemented with any text on rewrite systems, such as \cite{book2012string} or \cite{andallthat}. The algorithm is somewhat clever; to really ``get it'' might require several attempts. \index{Donald~Knuth}Donald~E.~Knuth and \index{Peter Bendix}Peter Bendix described the algorithm for term rewrite systems in a 1970 paper \cite{Knuth1983}; a correctness proof was later given by \index{Gerard Huet@G\'erard Huet}G\'erard Huet in \cite{HUET198111}. In our application, the terms are elements of a free monoid, so we have a string rewrite system; this special case was studied in \cite{narendran}. A survey of related techniques appears in \cite{BUCHBERGER19873}.
The entry point into the Knuth-Bendix completion procedure is Algorithm~\ref{knuthbendix}, but we break off four smaller pieces before we get there, so that only the top-level loop remains:
\begin{itemize}
\item Algorithm~\ref{overlap trie lookup} finds all rules that overlap with a fixed rule at a fixed position.
\item Algorithm~\ref{find overlapping rule algo} finds all pairs of rules that overlap at any position.
\item Algorithm~\ref{critical pair algo} builds a critical pair from a pair of overlapping rules.
\item Algorithm~\ref{add rule derived algo} resolves a critical pair.
\end{itemize}
We begin with Algorithm \ref{critical pair algo}~and~\ref{add rule derived algo}, proceeding from the inside out. The twin concepts of overlapping rule and critical pair are fundamental to the algorithm, and they provide the theoretical justification for the rest.
\paragraph{Local confluence.} We would like our \index{reduction relation}reduction relation $\rightarrow$ to satisfy the \index{Church-Rosser property}Church-Rosser property: if $x\sim y$ are two equivalent terms, then $x\rightarrow z$ and $y\rightarrow z$ for some term $z$. By Theorem~\ref{church rosser theorem}, this is equivalent to $\rightarrow$ being \index{confluence}confluent, meaning any two \index{positive rewrite path}positive rewrite paths diverging from a common source can be extended to meet each other. This is difficult to verify directly, but a 1941 paper by Max~Newman~\cite{newman} shows there is a simpler equivalent condition when the reduction relation is \index{terminating reduction relation}terminating.
\begin{definition}
A reduction relation $\rightarrow$ is \IndexDefinition{local confluence}\emph{locally confluent}, if whenever $s_1$ and $s_2$ are two positive rewrite steps with $\Src(s_1)=\Src(s_2)$, there exists a term $z$ such that $\Dst(s_1)\rightarrow z$ and $\Dst(s_2)\rightarrow z$.
\end{definition}
To test for local confluence, we ``diverge'' from a term by only one step in two different directions, and then check if both sides reduce to some common term. We will see this can be decided algorithmically, and also that we can ``repair'' any local \index{confluence violation}confluence violations we do find. Thus, \index{Newman's lemma}Newman's result is fundamental:
\begin{theorem}[Newman's Lemma]
If a reduction relation $\rightarrow$ is terminating and locally confluent, then $\rightarrow$ is confluent.
\end{theorem}
\paragraph{Overlapping rules.} A pair of positive rewrite steps with a common source define a \IndexDefinition{critical pair}\emph{critical pair}. A critical pair shows that some term can be reduced in ``two different ways.'' We can answer if our rewrite rules define a locally confluent reduction relation by inspecting each critical pair. With any non-trivial list of rewrite rules, there are infinitely many such critical pairs, however, all but a finite subset can be disregarded. Suppose we have a rewrite system over an alphabet $A$ with two rules:
\begin{gather*}
u_1\Rightarrow v_1\\
u_2\Rightarrow v_2
\end{gather*}
For any term $x\in A^*$, we can form the ``sandwich'' term $t := u_1xu_2$. Every such choice of $x$ defines a new critical pair; the occurrences of $u_1$ and $u_2$ within $t$ can be rewritten in two ways, by $s_1 := (u_1\Rightarrow v_1)xu_2$ and $s_2 := u_1x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)$. However, since $s_1$ and $s_2$ rewrite disjoint subterms of $t$, we say this critical pair is \IndexDefinition{orthogonal rewrite step}\emph{orthogonal}. Orthogonal critical pairs are not interesting because they cannot witness a local confluence violation. To see why, notice that regardless of whether we apply $s_1$ or $s_2$ first, there exists a complementary rewrite step $s_1^\prime$ or $s_2^\prime$ to rewrite $\Dst(s_1)$ or $\Dst(s_2)$ into the ``reduced sandwich'' $v_1xv_2$. In fact, we get a \index{commutative diagram}commutative diagram like this for any orthogonal critical pair:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&u_1xu_2\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "s_1:=(u_1\Rightarrow v_1)xu_2"', bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "s_2:=u_1x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)", bend left]\\
v_1xu_2\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "s_1^\prime := v_1x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)"', bend right]&&u_1xv_2\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "s_2^\prime:=v_1x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)", bend left]\\
&v_1xv_2
\end{tikzcd}
\]
We can also visualize an orthogonal critical pair using the ``pictorial'' notation for rewrite steps we devised in Section~\ref{rewrite graph}:
\[
\begin{array}{cc}
\text{$s_1$ first:}&
\text{$s_2$ first:}\\
\begin{array}{|c|c|c|}
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{u_1xu_2}\\
\hline
\hline
u_1&&\\
\Downarrow&y&u_2\\
v_1&&\\
\hline
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{v_1xu_2}\\
\hline
\hline
&&u_2\\
v_1&y&\Downarrow\\
&&v_2\\
\hline
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{v_1xv_2}\\
\hline
\end{array}
&
\begin{array}{|c|c|c|}
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{u_1xu_2}\\
\hline
\hline
&&u_2\\
u_1&y&\Downarrow\\
&&v_2\\
\hline
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{u_1xv_2}\\
\hline
\hline
u_1&&\\
\Downarrow&y&v_2\\
v_2&&\\
\hline
\hline
\multicolumn{3}{|c|}{v_1xv_2}\\
\hline
\end{array}
\end{array}
\]
Clearly, in our quest to uncover local \index{confluence violation}confluence violations, we only need to inspect critical pairs that are \emph{not} orthogonal; that is, they must rewrite \emph{overlapping} subterms of their common source term. There are only finitely many such critical pairs, and they are all generated by inspecting the left-hand sides of rewrite rules in our rewrite system. We can completely characterize them with the below definition.
\begin{definition}\label{overlappingrules}
Two rules $u_1\Rightarrow v_1$ and $u_2\Rightarrow v_2$ \IndexDefinition{overlapping rules}\emph{overlap} if one of the following holds:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The left-hand side of the second rule is contained entirely within the left-hand side of the first. That is, $u_1=xyz$ and $u_2=y$ for some $x$, $y$, $z\in A^*$. If we write down the terms $u_1$ and $u_2$ and shift $u_2$ over until they line up, we get this:
\begin{align*}
x&yz\\
&y
\end{align*}
\item The left-hand side of the second rule has a prefix equal to a suffix of the left-hand side of the first. That is, $u_1=xy$ and $u_2=yz$ for some $x$, $y$, $z\in A^*$, with $|x|>0$ and $|z|>0$. If we write down the terms $u_1$ and $u_2$ and shift $u_2$ over until they line up, we get this:
\begin{align*}
x&y\\
&yz
\end{align*}
\end{enumerate}
The above are the two ways in which a non-orthogonal critical pair can rewrite the same term. When the case distinction is important, we can talk about an overlap of the \emph{first kind}, or \emph{second kind}, respectively. In both cases, after a suitable assignment of $x$, $y$ and $z$, we define the \IndexDefinition{overlap term}\emph{overlap term} to be $xyz$, and the \IndexDefinition{overlap position}\emph{overlap position} to be $|x|$.
\end{definition}
\begin{example}
Consider these three rules:
\begin{gather*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\protosym{Equatable}\tag{1}\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{1}\tag{2}\\
\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\assocsym{Collection}{Element}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Collection}{Element}\tag{3}
\end{gather*}
There is an overlap of the first kind between (1) and (2) at position 0; the left-hand side of (2) is contained entirely in the left-hand side of (1). Here, the overlap term is $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\protosym{Equatable}$:
\begin{align*}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\protosym{Equatable}\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}
\end{align*}
There is an overlap of the second kind between (1) and (3) at position 1; the left-hand side of (3) begins with the prefix $\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}$, which is also a suffix of the left-hand side of (1). The overlap term is $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\protosym{Equatable}$:
\begin{align*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.&\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}\\
&\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\assocsym{Collection}{Element}
\end{align*}
The definition of an overlap of the second kind requires both $x$ and $z$ to be non-empty. If we relaxed this condition, then we would \emph{also} have an overlap of the second kind between rule (2) and (1) at position 0:
\begin{align*}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Collection}{SubSequence}.\protosym{Equatable}
\end{align*}
The overlap term and position is the same as the first case we saw already, so attempting to \index{resolving critical pair}resolve this critical pair would not reveal anything new. We adjust our definition to avoid duplicated work in this situation.
It can happen that two rules overlap more than once at \emph{different} positions; in this case we must consider every possible overlap. For example, these two rules generate four overlaps in total:
\begin{gather*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}\Rightarrow \assocsym{P}{C}\tag{4}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow \assocsym{P}{D}\tag{5}
\end{gather*}
Rule (4) overlaps with (5) at position 1:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.&\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}\\
&\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}
\end{align*}
Rrule (4) overlaps with (5) at position 3:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.&\assocsym{P}{B}\\
&\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}
\end{align*}
Rule (5) overlaps with (4) at position 1:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{B}.&\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}\\
&\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}
\end{align*}
Last but not least, rule (5) overlaps with (4) at position 3:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.&\assocsym{P}{A}\\
&\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}
\end{align*}
\end{example}
\paragraph{Resolving critical pairs.}
A critical pair exhibits some term $t$ being rewritten in two distinct ways. If we take the destination term of each of the two rewrite steps, we get a pair of terms that are known to be equivalent to $t$, and each other. For an overlap of the first kind, the two terms are $(v_1,\,xv_2z)$; for the second kind, $(v_1z,\,xv_2)$:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{cc}
Overlap of the first kind&
Overlap of the second kind\\
\begin{tikzcd}
&xyz\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(u_1\Rightarrow v_1)"', bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)z", bend left]\\
v_1&&xv_2z
\end{tikzcd}&
\begin{tikzcd}
&xyz\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(u_1\Rightarrow v_1)z"', bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)", bend left]\\
v_1z&&xv_2
\end{tikzcd}
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
We \IndexDefinition{resolving critical pair}\emph{resolve} a critical pair $(t_1,t_2)$ by reducing both sides with the reduction relation as constructed so far and comparing the reduced terms. There are four possible outcomes:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If $t_1$ and $t_2$ reduce to the same term $t^\prime$, we say the \IndexDefinition{trivial critical pair}critical pair is \emph{trivial}. (Note that this terminology offers an alternate definition of local confluence: a reduction relation is locally confluent if all critical pairs are trivial.)
\item If $t_1\rightarrow t_1^\prime$ and $t_2\rightarrow t_2^\prime$ with $t_1^\prime\neq t_2^\prime$, we found two distinct \index{reduced term}reduced terms in the same \index{equivalence class}equivalence class: a \index{confluence violation}\emph{confluence violation}. If $t_2^\prime < t_1^\prime$, we repair the confluence violation by adding a new rewrite rule $t_1^\prime\Rightarrow t_2^\prime$. Having done so, if we then define $t^\prime:=t_2^\prime$, we once again see that both $t_1$ and $t_2$ reduce to the same term $t^\prime$.
\item If instead $t_1^\prime<t_2^\prime$, we have the same situation except we resolve it by adding a new rewrite rule $t_2^\prime\Rightarrow t_1^\prime$, and we let $t^\prime:=t_1^\prime$.
\item If $t_1^\prime$ and $t_2^\prime$ are distinct but incomparable, we have a \index{non-orientable relation}non-orientable relation, and we must report an error. This cannot happen under the reduction order used by the Requirement Machine.
\end{enumerate}
We can draw a diagram for each case, showing a \index{subgraph}subgraph of the \index{rewrite graph}rewrite graph; dashed arrows indicate new rules being added:
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{ccc}
Trivial overlap&
Adding a new rule&
Adding a new rule\\
\begin{tikzcd}
&t\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
t_1\arrow[d, Rightarrow]&&t_2\arrow[d, Rightarrow]\\
\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]&&\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
&t^\prime
\end{tikzcd}&
\begin{tikzcd}
&t\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
t_1\arrow[d, Rightarrow]&&t_2\arrow[d, Rightarrow]\\
t_1^\prime\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, dashed, bend right]&&\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
&t^\prime
\end{tikzcd}&
\begin{tikzcd}
&t\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
t_1\arrow[d, Rightarrow]&&t_2\arrow[d, Rightarrow]\\
\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]&&t_2^\prime\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend left, dashed]\\
&t^\prime
\end{tikzcd}
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
After adding a new rewrite rule if necessary, we have a pair of rewrite paths $p_1$ and $p_2$, and a term $t^\prime$. Note that $\Src(p_1)=\Src(p_2)=t$ and $\Dst(p_1)=\Dst(p_2)=t^\prime$, so both paths have the same source and destination. We say $p_1$ and $p_2$ are \IndexDefinition{parallel rewrite paths}\emph{parallel} rewrite paths.
\paragraph{Rewrite loops.}
Now we slightly change our point of view and introduce a new concept. If we take two parallel rewrite paths $p_1$ and $p_2$, we can form the rewrite path $\ell:=p_1\circ p_2^{-1}$ by composing the first path with the inverse of the second:
\[
\begin{array}{ccc}
\text{$p_1$:}&\text{$p_2$:}&\text{$p_1\circ p_2^{-1}$}\\
\begin{tikzcd}
&t\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
&t^\prime
\end{tikzcd}&
\begin{tikzcd}
t\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
&\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
t^\prime
\end{tikzcd}&
\begin{tikzcd}
&t\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]&&\vphantom{P}\cdots\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
&t^\prime\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\end{array}
\]
This new rewrite path $\ell$ has the property that it begins and ends at the \emph{same} term $t$:
\begin{gather*}
\Src(\ell)=\Src(p_1)=t\qquad\qquad\Dst(\ell)=\Dst(p_2^{-1})=\Src(p_2)=t
\end{gather*}
We say that $\ell$ is a \IndexDefinition{rewrite loop}\emph{rewrite loop} with \IndexDefinition{basepoint}basepoint $t$. A rewrite loop applies some sequence of rewrite rules to the basepoint term $t$, then rewrites it ``back'' to $t$, via a possibly \emph{different} mix of rewrite rules. In the \index{rewrite graph}rewrite graph, a rewrite loop is a \index{cycle}cycle (sometimes called a ``closed path'' by graph theorists). Note that for each $t\in A^*$, the \index{empty rewrite path}empty rewrite path $1_t$ can also be seen as a trivial rewrite loop with basepoint $t$.
Now, we give two algorithms that together form the inner loop of the completion procedure. It is also convenient to view a \index{critical pair}critical pair as a rewrite path of length 2, rather than a pair of rewrite steps with the same source term---we compose the first step with the inverse of the second. In this new formulation, critical pair resolution ``completes'' the critical pair to form a rewrite loop.
\begin{algorithm}[Construct critical pair]\label{critical pair algo}
Takes two rules $u_1\Rightarrow v_1$ and $u_2\Rightarrow v_2$, together with an overlap position $i$ where $0\leq i<|u_1|$. Returns a triple $(t_1, t_2, p)$ where $t_1$ and $t_2$ are terms, and $p$ is a rewrite path with $\Src(p)=t_1$ and $\Dst(p)=t_2$.
\begin{enumerate}
\item If $i+|u_2|\leq|u_1|$, we have an overlap of the first kind; $u_1=xu_2z$ for some $x$ and $z$.
\begin{enumerate}
\item Let $x:=u_1[:i]$ (the prefix of $u_1$ of length $i$), and $z:=u_1[i+|u_2|:]$ (the suffix of $u_1$ of length $|u_1|-|u_2|-i$).
\item Set $t_1:=v_1$, the result of rewriting $u_1$ with the first rule.
\item Set $t_2:=xv_2z$, the result of rewriting $u_1$ with the second rule.
\item Set $p:=(v_1\Rightarrow u_1)\circ x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)z$. This is a rewrite path from $t_1$ to $t_2$.
\end{enumerate}
\item Otherwise, we have an overlap of the second kind; $u_1=xy$ and $u_2=yz$ for some $x$, $y$ and $z$.
\begin{enumerate}
\item Let $x:=u_1[:i]$ (the prefix of $u_1$ of length $i$), $z:=u_2[|u_1|-i:]$ (the suffix of $u_2$ of length $|u_2|-|u_1|+i$). (We don't actually need $y:=u_1[i:]=u_2[:|u_1|-i]$.)
\item Set $t_1:=v_1z$, the result of rewriting $xyz$ with the first rule.
\item Set $t_2:=xv_2$, the result of rewriting $xyz$ with the second rule.
\item Set $p:=(v_1\Rightarrow u_1)z\circ x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)$.
\end{enumerate}
\item Return the triple $(t_1, t_2, p)$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
\begin{algorithm}[Resolve critical pair]\label{add rule derived algo}
As input, takes terms $t_1$ and $t_2$, and a rewrite path $p$ with $\Src(p)=t_1$ and $\Dst(p)=t_2$. Records a rewrite loop, and possibly adds a new rule, returning true if a rule was added.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Fast path) If $t_1=t_2$, $p$ is already a loop; record it and return false.
\item (Left) Apply Algorithm~\ref{term reduction trie algo} to $t_1$, to reduce $t_1\rightarrow t_1^\prime$ with rewrite path $p_1$.
\item (Right) Apply Algorithm~\ref{term reduction trie algo} to $t_2$, to reduce $t_2\rightarrow t_2^\prime$ with rewrite path $p_2$.
\item (Compare) Use Algorithm~\ref{rqm reduction order} to compare $t_1^\prime$ with $t_2^\prime$.
\item (Trivial) \index{trivial critical pair}If $t_1^\prime=t_2^\prime$, record a loop $p_1^{-1}\circ p\circ p_2$ with basepoint $t_1^\prime=t_2^\prime$, and return false.
\item (Smaller) If $t_2^\prime<t_1^\prime$, add the rule $t_1^\prime\Rightarrow t_2^\prime$, record a loop $p_2^{-1}\circ p^{-1}\circ p_1\circ (t_1^\prime\Rightarrow t_2^\prime)$ with basepoint $t_1^\prime$, and return true.
\item (Larger) If $t_1^\prime<t_2^\prime$, add the rule $t_2^\prime\Rightarrow t_1^\prime$, record a loop $p_1^{-1}\circ p \circ p_2 \circ (t_2^\prime\Rightarrow t_1^\prime)$ with basepoint $t_2^\prime$, and return true.
\item (Error) Otherwise, $t_1^\prime$ and $t_2^\prime$ are incomparable; signal an error.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
Rewrite loops are not just a theoretical tool; our implementation of the Knuth-Bendix algorithm follows \cite{loggedrewriting} and \cite{homotopicalcompletion} in encoding and recording the rewrite loops that describe resolved critical pairs. This enables the computation of minimal requirements in Section~\ref{homotopy reduction}. Only local rules are subject to \index{requirement minimization}minimization, so we only record rewrite loops involving local rules. If a requirement machine instance is only to be used for generic signature queries and not minimization, rewrite loops are not recorded at all.
\paragraph{An optimization.}
Now that we know how to process a single overlap and resolve a critical pair, the next chunk of code concerns enumerating all candidate overlaps. In an arbitrary string rewrite system, we must consider all possible combinations: for every rewrite rule $u_1\Rightarrow v_1$, for every rewrite rule $u_2\Rightarrow v_2$, and for every position $i<|u_1|$, we would need to check if the corresponding subterms of $u_1$ and $u_2$ are identical. In our application, the bottom-up construction of a rewrite system from protocol components, and the partition of rewrite rules into \index{imported rule}imported rules and \index{local rule}local rules, enables an optimization where overlaps between certain pairs of rules need not be considered at all:
\begin{itemize}
\item We don't need to look for overlaps between imported rules. While an imported rule can overlap with another imported rule, all such critical pairs are trivial and do not need to be resolved again.
\item We don't need to look for overlaps between an imported rule and a local rule. An imported rule cannot overlap with a local rule.
\end{itemize}
Only two interesting pairings remain:
\begin{itemize}
\item A local rule can overlap with another local rule.
\item A local rule can overlap with an imported rule.
\end{itemize}
We now proceed to prove that this is indeed the case. First, suppose two imported rules overlap. We will consider three possibilities in turn:
\begin{itemize}
\item There is an overlap of the first kind.
\item There is an overlap of the second kind, and the second rule's left-hand side starts with an associated type symbol.
\item There is an overlap of the second kind, and the second rule's left-hand side starts with a protocol symbol.
\end{itemize}
In all three cases, we will conclude that both rules either originate from the same \index{protocol component}protocol component, or two distinct components where one imports the other. This implies that the \index{trivial critical pair}critical pair is now trivial, having been resolved by completion of that protocol component which contains the other.
In the first case, it is immediate that both rules were imported from the same protocol component for \texttt{P}:
\begin{align*}
&\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\\
&\assocsym{P}{A}
\end{align*}
In the second case, \texttt{P} and \texttt{Q} are either in the same protocol component, or \texttt{Q} is a protocol dependency of \texttt{P}, because we have $G_\texttt{P}\vDash\ConfReq{Self.A}{Q}$:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.&\assocsym{Q}{B}\\
&\assocsym{Q}{B}.\assocsym{R}{C}
\end{align*}
The final case similarly implies that \texttt{Q} is a protocol dependency of \texttt{P}:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.&\protosym{Q}\\
&\protosym{Q}.\protosym{R}
\end{align*}
Next, we claim that imported rules cannot overlap with local rules. In a generic signature rewrite system, the local rules are precisely those whose left-hand side starts with a \index{generic parameter symbol}generic parameter symbol. The left-hand side of an imported rule cannot start with, or contain, a generic parameter symbol, proving the claim. In a protocol component rewrite system, we can similarly rule out overlap of the first kind between an imported rule and a local rule, because the two rules must start with the same \index{protocol symbol}protocol or \index{associated type symbol}associated type symbol, and thus originate from the same protocol component. Now, suppose a protocol component rewrite system has an overlap of the second kind. We show that if the second rule, the one with left-hand side $\assocsym{Q}{B}.\assocsym{R}{C}$, is a local rule, then the first rule is as well:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.&\assocsym{Q}{B}\\
&\assocsym{Q}{B}.\assocsym{R}{C}
\end{align*}
As before, \texttt{Q} must be a \index{protocol dependency graph}protocol dependency of \texttt{P}. But this time, we have the further assumption that \texttt{Q} belongs to the \emph{current} protocol component, so the appearance of \texttt{P} means that \texttt{P} must \emph{also} be a protocol dependency of \texttt{Q}. Thus, \texttt{P} and \texttt{Q} depend on each other, and are actually part of the same component; therefore both rules are local.
\paragraph{Another optimization.} If we fix a rule and position, we can find all overlaps involving this rule and position by performing a lookup into the rule trie, which we previously used to speed up term reduction in Section~\ref{term reduction}. This further cuts down the work in enumerating overlaps. While the underlying data structure is the same, the lookup algorithm here differs from that used by term reduction; we must enumerate all matches, instead of stopping after the first one.
Consider a set of rewrite rules having the terms $a$, $ab$, $bc$, $bd$ and $acd$ as their left-hand sides. The rule with left-hand side $ab$ has overlaps with all other rules except for $acd$. Here is the rule trie, with thick borders denoting nodes associated with rewrite rules:
\[
\begin{tikzpicture}
[level distance=10mm,
every node/.style={fill=light-gray!60,circle,inner sep=1pt},
level 1/.style={sibling distance=30mm},
level 2/.style={sibling distance=20mm},
level 3/.style={sibling distance=10mm}]
\node [rounded corners, rectangle] {\strut root}
child {node [thick, draw=black] {$\strut a$}
child {node [thick, draw=black] {$\strut b$}}
child {node {$\strut c$}
child {node [thick, draw=black] {$\strut d$}}
}
}
child {node {$\strut b$}
child {node [thick, draw=black] {$\strut c$}}
child {node [thick, draw=black] {$\strut d$}}
};
\end{tikzpicture}
\]
When checking the left-hand side $ab$ for overlaps, we perform two lookups:
\begin{itemize}
\item At position 0, we look up $ab$. Starting from the root, we encounter the rule for $a$, followed by $ab$ (which is the left-hand side of our rule itself, so we skip it). The latter node is a leaf so we end the search.
\item At position 1, we look up $b$. The node for $b$ doesn't store a rewrite rule, however, it has child nodes. We've reached the end of our input sequence, so we recursively visit all children, and find the two final overlap candidates, $bc$ and $bd$.
\end{itemize}
This new kind of trie lookup can be thought of as a \index{coroutine}coroutine or an iterator, yielding zero or more results as the search proceeds. We implement it as a higher-order function taking a callback.
\begin{algorithm}[Overlap lookup in rule trie]\label{overlap trie lookup}
Takes a term $t$, position $i$ with $0\leq i<|t|$, and a callback. For each rule $u\Rightarrow v$ where $t[i:]$ is a prefix of $u$ or $u$ is a prefix of $t[i:]$, invokes the callback with the rule $u\Rightarrow v$.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Initialize) Set \texttt{N} to the root node of the trie.
\item (End) If $i=|t|$, we've reached the end of the term. Perform a pre-order traversal of all child nodes of \texttt{N}, and for those children that have an associated rewrite rule, invoke the callback with that rule (this is the case where $t[i:]$ is a prefix of each $u$).
\item (Traverse) Let $s_i$ be the $i$th symbol of $t$. Let \texttt{M} be the child node of \texttt{N} associated with $s_i$. If the lookup fails, return.
\item (Child) Otherwise, if \texttt{M} has an associated rule $u\Rightarrow v$, invoke the callback with this rule (in this case, $u$ is a prefix of $t[i:]$).
\item (Advance) Set $\texttt{N}:=\texttt{M}$. Increment $i$ and go back to Step~2.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
The next algorithm feeds the results of Algorithm~\ref{overlap trie lookup} into Algorithm~\ref{critical pair algo} to build a list of all critical pairs in the rewrite system. After \index{resolving critical pair}resolving these critical pairs, we will have to check for overlaps again, in case there are any involving the newly-added rules. To avoid repeated work, the below algorithm maintains a set of visited overlaps, so that we can avoid building and resolving a critical pair we already know has been resolved.
\begin{algorithm}[Finding overlapping rules]\label{find overlapping rule algo}
Takes a rewrite system as input, and outputs a list of critical pairs. Also queries and updates the set of visited overlaps.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Initialize) Set $n:=0$. Let \texttt{N} be the number of local rules in the rewrite system. Initialize an empty output list.
\item (Outer check) If $n=\texttt{N}$, we're done. Return the output list.
\item (Get rule) Denote the $n$th local rule in the rewrite system by $u_1\Rightarrow v_1$ (not a typo; that's 1 not $n$). If this rule is marked as \index{left-simplified rule}\textbf{left-simplified}, \index{right-simplified rule}\textbf{right-simplified} or \index{substitution-simplified rule}\textbf{substitution-simplified}, skip it entirely and go to Step~7. Otherwise, set $i:=0$.
\item (Inner check) If $i=|u_1|$, we're done. Go to Step~9.
\item (Find overlaps) Use Algorithm~\ref{overlap trie lookup} to find all rules whose left-hand side is a prefix of the symbol range $u_1[i:]$ or vice versa.
\item (Visit) For each matching rule $u_2\Rightarrow v_2$ found above, check if this rule is marked as \textbf{left-simplified}, \textbf{right-simplified} or \textbf{substitution-simplified}. Also, check if $(u_1\Rightarrow v_1,\,u_2\Rightarrow v_2,\,i)$ is already in the visited set. In either case, move on to the next matching rule.
\item (Record) Otherwise, add $(u_1\Rightarrow v_1,\,u_2\Rightarrow v_2,\,i)$ to the visited set, and build a critical pair for this overlap using Algorithm~\ref{critical pair algo}. This produces a triple $(t_1, t_2, p)$ describing the critical pair; add this critical pair to the output list.
\item (Inner loop) Increment $i$, and go back to Step~3.
\item (Outer loop) Increment $n$, and go back to Step~2.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
We can now describe the main loop of the Knuth-Bendix completion procedure, which repeatedly finds and resolves critical pairs until no more non-trivial critical pairs remain. This process might not terminate, and we might find ourselves discovering new critical pairs and adding new rules to resolve them, forever. To prevent an infinite loop in the case of failure, we implement a termination check; if we think we've done too much work already, we give up on constructing a covergent rewrite system. We already mentioned the \textbf{left-simplified}, \textbf{right-simplified}, and \textbf{substitution-simplified} flags a few times; they are set by the rule simplification passes, with the first two described in Section~\ref{rule reduction} and the third one in Section~\ref{subst simplification}. These passes are invoked at appropriate times in the main loop below.
\begin{algorithm}[Knuth-Bendix completion procedure]\label{knuthbendix} Takes a rewrite system as input, and outputs success or failure. On success, the rewrite system is now convergent, with all resolved critical pairs described by recorded rewrite loops. Failure occurs if we encounter a non-orientable relation, or if we trigger the termination check.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Initialize) Clear the flag.
\item (Overlaps) Use Algorithm~\ref{find overlapping rule algo} to build a list of critical pairs.
\item (Left simpify) Invoke Algorithm~\ref{left simplification}.
\item (Resolve) For each critical pair, invoke Algorithm~\ref{add rule derived algo} and set the flag if any new rewrite rules were added.
\item (Right simplify) Invoke Algorithm~\ref{right simplification}.
\item (Substitution simplify) Invoke Algorithm~\ref{subst simplification algo}.
\item (Termination) If we exceeded the rule count, term length or concrete nesting limits, return failure.
\item (Repeat) If the flag was set, go back to Step~1. Otherwise, return success.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
\paragraph{Termination.} \index{limitation}Our termination check is controlled by a handful of command-line flags:
\begin{itemize}
\item \IndexFlag{requirement-machine-max-rule-count} \texttt{-requirement-machine-max-rule-count} controls the maximum number of local rules. Imported rules do not count toward this total, so this is hard to hit with realistic code. The default is a maximum of 4000 local rules.
\item \IndexFlag{requirement-machine-max-rule-length} \texttt{-requirement-machine-max-rule-count} controls the maximum length of a rule's left-hand side. To compute the actual quantity, we add the length of the longest \emph{user-written} rule; so the restriction in on the relative ``growth'' and not on the length of a type parameter written by the user. The default value is 12.
\item \IndexFlag{requirement-machine-max-concrete-nesting} \texttt{-requirement-machine-max-concrete-nesting} controls the maximum nesting of concrete types, to prevent \index{substitution simplification}substitution simplification from constructing an infinite type like \texttt{G<G<G<...>>>}. This is an absolute limit, so we will arbitrarily reject user-written requirements with deeply-nested concrete types. The default value is 30.
\end{itemize}
In a runaway critical pairs scenario, it can take several seconds for completion to reach the rule count limit. The rule length limit enables earlier detection of situations where completion has clearly gone off the rails. The rule length limit being relative instead of just a total ban on terms of length 12 allows various pathological cases to succeed which would otherwise be needlessly rejected. We can type check a protocol representing the monoid $\mathbb{Z}/14\mathbb{Z}$ without fear:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol Z14 {
associatedtype A: Z14
where Self == Self.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A.A
}
\end{Verbatim}
A future improvement would be to change the concrete nesting limit to also be relative to the complexity of user-written requirements. There is no technical reason not to support deeply-nested concrete types here, it is only needed to catch runaway substitution simplification.
If completion fails when building a rewrite system for \index{requirement minimization}minimization, we have a source location associated with some protocol or generic declaration. An error is diagnosed at this source location, and we proceed with minimization producing an empty list of requirements. If completion fails on a rewrite system built from an existing generic signature or \index{protocol component}protocol component, there is no source location we can use for diagnostics; the compiler dumps the entire rewrite system and aborts with a fatal error. The latter scenario is unusual; if we successfully constructed a generic signature from user-written requirements, we should be able to build a rewrite system for it again.
\paragraph{Debugging flags}
A pair of debugging options can help us understand the operation of the completion procedure; both can be set together\footnote{With a single \texttt{-debug-requirement-machine=} flag, separating the subflags with commas.}, but be warned that they produce a large volume of output:
\begin{itemize}
\item \IndexTwoFlag{debug-requirement-machine}{completion} \texttt{-debug-requirement-machine=completion} will dump all overlapping rules and critical pairs.
\item \IndexTwoFlag{debug-requirement-machine}{add} \texttt{-debug-requirement-machine=add} will dump all rewrite rules and rewrite loops obtained while resolving critical pairs.
\end{itemize}
\newcommand{\AssocIntro}[2]{\protosym{#1}.\texttt{#2}\Rightarrow\assocsym{#1}{#2}}
\newcommand{\AssocIntroInv}[2]{\assocsym{#1}{#2}\Rightarrow\protosym{#1}.\texttt{#2}}
\newcommand{\InheritAssocIntro}[3]{\protosym{#1}.\assocsym{#2}{#3}\Rightarrow\assocsym{#1}{#3}}
\newcommand{\InheritAssocIntroInv}[3]{\assocsym{#1}{#3}\Rightarrow\protosym{#1}.\assocsym{#2}{#3}}
\newcommand{\ProtoConf}[2]{#1.\protosym{#2}\Rightarrow #1}
\newcommand{\ProtoConfInv}[2]{#1\Rightarrow #1.\protosym{#2}}
\newcommand{\ProtoInherit}[2]{\ProtoConf{\protosym{#1}}{#2}}
\newcommand{\ProtoInheritInv}[2]{\ProtoConfInv{\protosym{#1}}{#2}}
\newcommand{\FourLoopDerived}[8]{%
\begin{tikzcd}[ampersand replacement=\&]%
\\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "#5"', bend right]\&\\
#2\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "#6"', bend right, dashed]\&\\arrow[lu, Rightarrow,"#8"', bend right]\\
\\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, "#7"', bend right]\&
\end{tikzcd}}
\newcommand{\FourLoopDerivedOther}[8]{%
\begin{tikzcd}[ampersand replacement=\&]%
\\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "#5"', bend right]\&\\
#2\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "#6"', bend right]\&\\arrow[lu, Rightarrow,"#8"', bend right]\\
\\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, "#7"', bend right, dashed]\&
\end{tikzcd}}
\newcommand{\FourLoopTrivial}[8]{%
\begin{tikzcd}[ampersand replacement=\&]%
\\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "#5"', bend right]\&\\
#2\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, "#6"', bend right]\&\\arrow[lu, Rightarrow,"#8"', bend right]\\
\\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, "#7"', bend right]\&
\end{tikzcd}}
\section{Rule Simplification}\label{rule reduction}
We impose two further conditions on our \index{convergent rewrite system}convergent rewrite system:
\begin{enumerate}
\item No rule has a left-hand side that can be reduced by any other rule.
\item No rule has a right-hand side that can be reduced by any other rule.
\end{enumerate}
Such rewrite systems are called \IndexDefinition{left-reduced rewrite system}\emph{left-reduced} or \IndexDefinition{right-reduced rewrite system}\emph{right-reduced}, respectively, or simply \emph{reduced} if both conditions are met. Any convergent rewrite system can be transformed into a reduced rewrite system with a pair of simplification passes that possibly delete and add rules.
In our implementation, we don't \emph{actually} delete rules, because we use the index of each rule as a stable reference elsewhere; instead, we set a pair of rule flags, \index{left-simplified rule}\textbf{left-simplified} and \index{right-simplified rule}\textbf{right-simplified}, and delete the rule from the \index{rule trie}\index{trie}rule trie. We've seen these flags mentioned already, so now we reveal their purpose. This will motivate the subsequent theory, setting the stage for the remaining two sections of this chapter.
\paragraph{Left simplification.} If the left-hand side of a rewrite rule $u_1\Rightarrow v_1$ can be reduced by another rewrite rule $u_2\Rightarrow v_2$, then $u_1=xu_2z$ for some $x$, $z\in A^*$, so we have an \index{overlapping rules}overlap of the first kind in the sense of Definition~\ref{overlappingrules}. Once we resolve all critical pairs, we don't need the first rule at all; we know that in a convergent rewrite system, both ways of reducing the overlap term $u_1:=xu_2z$ produce the same result:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&u_1
\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right, "(u_1\Rightarrow v_1)"']
\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left, "x(u_2\Rightarrow v_2)z"]
\\
v_1\arrow[d, Rightarrow]&&xv_2z\arrow[d, Rightarrow]\\
\ldots\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]&&\ldots\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
&t^\prime&
\end{tikzcd}
\]
The \IndexDefinition{left simplification}left simplification algorithm considers the left-hand side of each rule, and marks the rule if it finds a subterm matching some other rule.
\begin{algorithm}[Left-simplify rewrite system]\label{left simplification}
Takes a rewrite system as input. Sets rule flags and modifies the rule trie as needed.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Initialize) Let \texttt{N} be the number of local rules in our rewrite system, and set $i:=0$.
\item (Outer check) If $i=\texttt{N}$, return. Otherwise, say $u\Rightarrow v$ is the $i$th rule in \texttt{R}, and set $j:=0$.
\item (Inner check) If $j=|u|$, go to Step~8.
\item (Search) Look up $u[:j]$ in the \index{rule trie}rule \index{trie}trie, where $u[:j]$ is the suffix of $u$ of length $|u|-j$.
\item (Decide) If the trie lookup returns no results, or it returns $u\Rightarrow v$ itself (which can only happen if $j=0$, so $u[:j]=u$), go to Step~7.
\item (Mark) Otherwise, $u$ has a subterm equal to the left-hand side of some other rule. Mark $u\Rightarrow v$ as \textbf{left-simplified}, remove it from the rule trie, and go to Step~7.
\item (Inner loop) Increment $j$ and go back to Step~3.
\item (Outer loop) Increment $i$ and go back to Step~2.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
\paragraph{Right simplification.} The other case is when we have a rule $u\Rightarrow v$ whose right-hand side $v$ is not reduced, so $v\rightarrow v^\prime$ via some \index{positive rewrite path}positive rewrite path $p_v$. Now suppose we have a positive rewrite path $x(u\Rightarrow v)z\circ p$, where $\Dst(p)$ is some reduced term $t^\prime$. If we reduce $xuz$ to $xvz$ via $x(u\Rightarrow v)z$, we have two choices on how to proceed: we can follow $p$, or reduce $xvz$ to $xv^\prime z$ via \index{whiskering}$x\star p_v \star z$. By confluence, the second choice must take us to $t^\prime$ via a positive rewrite path $p^\prime$ with $\Src(p^\prime)=xv^\prime z$ and $\Dst(p^\prime)=t^\prime$. Thus, we record a new rule $u\Rightarrow v^\prime$ that obsoletes $u\Rightarrow v$:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&xuz\arrow[dd, Rightarrow, "x(u\Rightarrow v)z"']\arrow[rrddd, Rightarrow, bend left, "x(u\Rightarrow v^\prime)z", dashed]&\\
&\arrow[d, Rightarrow]&\\
&xvz\arrow[dd, Rightarrow, "p"']\arrow[rrd, Rightarrow, "x\star p_v\star z"', bend left]\\
&&&xv^\prime z\arrow[lld, "p^\prime", Rightarrow, bend left]\\
&t^\prime&
\end{tikzcd}
\]
The \IndexDefinition{right simplification}right simplification algorithm outputs a right-reduced rewrite system by attempting to reduce the right-hand side of each rewrite rule. While left simplification does not need to record new rewrite rules because completion has already resolved all overlaps of the first kind, right simplification actually records new rules as well as marking existing rules as having been simplified. The new rule is related with the existing rule by a rewrite loop:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&v\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(v\Rightarrow u)"', bend right]&\\
u\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, "(u\Rightarrow v^\prime)"', dashed, bend right]&&v^\prime\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, "p_v^{-1}"', bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\]
\begin{algorithm}[Right-simplify rewrite system]\label{right simplification}
Takes a rewrite system as input, and modifies its rules as needed.
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Initialize) Let \texttt{N} be the number of local rules in our rewrite system, and set $i:=0$.
\item (Check) If $i=\texttt{N}$, return. Otherwise, let $u\Rightarrow v$ be the $i$th local rule.
\item (Reduce) Apply Algorithm~\ref{term reduction trie algo} to $v$ to get a rewrite path $p_v$. If $p_v$ is the \index{empty rewrite path}empty rewrite path $1_{v}$, the right-hand side $v$ is already reduced, so go to Step~7.
\item (Record) Let $v^\prime=\Dst(p_v)$. Add a new rewrite rule $u\Rightarrow v^\prime$ to the list of local rules, and insert it into the rule trie with the key $u$, replacing the old rule $u\Rightarrow v$.
\item (Relate) Add the rewrite loop $(u\Rightarrow v)\circ p\circ(v^\prime\Rightarrow u)$ with basepoint $u$, relating the old rule $u\Rightarrow v$ with the new rule $u\Rightarrow v^\prime$.
\item (Mark) Mark the old rule as \textbf{right-simplified}.
\item (Loop) Increment $i$ and go back to Step~2.
\end{enumerate}
\end{algorithm}
Our justification for the validity of these passes worked from the assumption that we had a convergent rewrite system; that is, that completion had already been performed. In practice, Algorithm~\ref{knuthbendix} repeatedly runs both passes during completion, once per round of \index{critical pair}critical pair resolution. This is advantageous, because we can subsequently avoid considering overlaps that involve simplified rules. This strategy remains sound as long as we perform left simplification after computing critical pairs, but \emph{before} resolving them, which might add new rules. This narrows the candidates for left simplification to those rules whose overlaps have already been considered. As for the right simplification pass, it is actually fine to run it at any point; we choose to run it after \index{resolving critical pair}resolving critical pairs.
\paragraph{Related concepts.}
We previously saw in Section~\ref{minimal requirements} that the same-type requirements in a generic signature are subject to similar conditions of being left-reduced and right-reduced. There is a connection here, because as we will see in Section~\ref{requirement builder}, the minimal requirements of a generic signature are ultimately constructed from the rules of a reduced rewrite system. However, there are a few notational differences:
\begin{itemize}
\item The roles of ``left'' and ``right'' are reversed because requirements use a different convention; in a reduced same-type requirement $\FormalReq{U == V}$, we have $\texttt{U} < \texttt{V}$, whereas in a rewrite rule $u\Rightarrow v$ we have $v<u$.
\item Reduced same-type requirements have the ``shortest'' distance between the left-hand and right-hand side, so if \texttt{T}, \texttt{U} and \texttt{V} are all equivalent and $\texttt{T}<\texttt{U}<\texttt{V}$, the corresponding requirements are $\FormalReq{T == U}$, $\FormalReq{U == V}$. On the other hand, if we have three terms $t$, $u$ and $v$ with $t<u<v$, then the two corresponding rewrite rules would be $u\Rightarrow t$, $v\Rightarrow t$.
\end{itemize}
These differences are explained by the original \Index{GenericSignatureBuilder@\texttt{GenericSignatureBuilder}}\texttt{GenericSignatureBuilder} minimization algorithm, described as finding a minimum \index{spanning tree}spanning tree for a graph of connected components. The notion of reduced requirement output by this algorithm became part of the Swift stable \index{ABI}ABI. In Section~\ref{requirement builder} we show that a list of rewrite rules in a reduced rewrite system defines a list of reduced requirements via a certain transformation.
What we call reduced rewrite systems are sometimes ``normalized'', ``canonical'', or ``inter-reduced'' in the literature. Our rewrite system also implements a third \emph{substitution simplification} pass for rewrite system simplification. Substitution simplification reduces substitution terms appearing in superclass, concrete type and concrete conformance symbols. We will discuss it in Chapter~\ref{propertymap}.
\section{Associated Types}\label{critical pairs}
A conformance rule $t.\protosym{P}\Rightarrow t$ always overlaps with an associated type introduction rule $\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}$, and resolving this critical pair defines a rule $t.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow t.\assocsym{P}{A}$ (unless something further reduces the right-hand side). These rewrite rules reduce those terms representing \index{unbound type parameter}unbound type parameters to \index{bound type parameter}bound type parameters. Thus, we will see how the bound and unbound type parameters from Section~\ref{reducedtypes} manifest in our rewrite system.
\begin{example}\label{assoc type completion example}
We're going to look at this pair of protocol declarations, and the \index{protocol generic signature}protocol generic signature $G_\texttt{P}$:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol Q {
associatedtype B
}
protocol P {
associatedtype A: Q
}
\end{Verbatim}
Protocol \texttt{P} has an \index{associated conformance requirement}associated conformance requirement $\ConfReq{Self.[P]A}{Q}_\texttt{P}$, and $G_\texttt{P}$ has a conformance requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}$, so the \index{protocol dependency graph}protocol dependency graph has the two edges $G_\texttt{P}\prec\texttt{P}$ and $\texttt{P}\prec\texttt{Q}$. We first build a rewrite system for \texttt{Q}. The rewrite system for $G_\texttt{P}$ imports rules from \texttt{P} and \texttt{Q}:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\AssocIntro{Q}{B}\tag{1}&\\
\midrule
&\AssocIntro{P}{A}\tag{2}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{A}}{Q}\tag{3}&\\
&\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\tag{*4}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}\tag{5}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}\tag{*6}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
We can categorize these rewrite rules as follows:
\begin{itemize}
\item Associated type introduction rules: (1) and (2).
\item Conformance requirements: (3) and (5).
\item Rules added by completion are indicated with an asterisk: (*4) and (*6).
\end{itemize}
We omit the identity conformance rules $\ProtoConf{\protosym{Q}}{Q}$ and $\ProtoConf{\protosym{P}}{P}$; in this example they would only clutter the presentation. They will serve a useful purpose later, in Example~\ref{proto assoc rule}.
We now go through the construction step by step. Protocol \texttt{Q} does not depend on any other protocols. The rewrite system for \texttt{Q} is just rule (1):
\begin{gather*}
\AssocIntro{Q}{B}\tag{1}
\end{gather*}
Protocol \texttt{P} imports the single rule of \texttt{Q}, and adds rules (2) and (3):
\begin{gather*}
\AssocIntro{P}{A}\tag{2}\\
\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{A}}{Q}\tag{3}
\end{gather*}
We need to check the left-hand side of rules (2) and (3) for overlaps with other rules. Rule (2) does not overlap with any other rules. Rule (3) overlaps with rule (1) on the term $\assocsym{P}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{B}$:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.&\protosym{Q}\\
&\protosym{Q}.\texttt{B}
\end{align*}
Rule (3) is local to \texttt{P}, while (1) was imported from \texttt{Q}. The two sides of the critical pair reduce to $\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}$ and $\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$. Resolving this critical pair introduces rule (*4):
\[
\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\tag{*4}
\]
We also record a rewrite loop that defines rule (*4) via rules (3) and (1):
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\assocsym{P}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{B}
\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{A}}{Q}).\texttt{B}"']\\
\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed, "(\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B})"']
&&
\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right, "\assocsym{P}{A}.(\AssocIntroInv{Q}{B})"']
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Once again, we check for overlaps in the left-hand sides of our local rules---now (2), (3) and (4). We see that no more critical pairs remain, and we have a convergent rewrite system for \texttt{P}.
Finally, we build the rewrite system for $G_\texttt{P}$. We import all rules from \texttt{Q} and \texttt{P}, and add one new local rule corresponding to the conformance requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}$:
\[
\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}\tag{5}
\]
We need to check the left-hand side of rule (5) for overlaps with other rules. Indeed, rule (5) overlaps with rule (2) on the term
$\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.&\protosym{P}\\
&\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair introduces rule (*6):
\[
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}\tag{*6}
\]
We also record a rewrite loop that defines rule (*6) via rules (5) and (2):
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}).\texttt{A}"', bend right]\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A})"', bend right, dashed]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}\arrow[ul, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntroInv{P}{A})"', bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\]
At this point, there might be overlaps involving one of rule (5) or (*6); a quick check shows none remain, so we have a convergent rewrite system for $G_\texttt{P}$.
Now, we get to the interesting part. Consider these two type parameters of $G_\texttt{P}$, and their corresponding \index{type-like term}type-like terms:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The unbound type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}, and term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}$.
\item The bound type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B}, and term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$.
\end{enumerate}
The second term is reduced, so the first term must reduce to the second term. Term reduction outputs a \index{positive rewrite path}positive rewrite path $p$ with $\Src(p)=\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}$ and $\Dst(p)=\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$. This path involves rules (4) and (6) added by completion:
\[
p := (\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}).\texttt{B} \circ \ttgp{0}{0}.(\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{B}{Q})
\]
Here is a diagram for $p$:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}[column sep=huge]
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[r, Rightarrow]&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[r, Rightarrow]&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}
\end{tikzcd}
\]
There is a ``telescoping'' effect, as term reduction processes the name symbols from left to right, replacing them with associated type symbols. As an aside, if we have an \emph{invalid} type parameter, such as \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A}, the term reduces to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{A}$ but no further; the final name symbol \texttt{A} cannot be ``resolved'' because the type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A} does not \emph{have} a member type named \texttt{A}.
The type-like term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}$ reduces to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$ because the unbound type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.B} is equivalent to the bound type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B}, and the latter is the reduced type of the former. The equivalence follows because we can derive a same-type requirement, and the left-hand side of this same-type requirement is the reduced type because no smaller type parameter can be shown to be equivalent:
\[G_\texttt{P}\vDash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B == \ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}\]
Here is one possible derivation for this same-type requirement:
\begin{gather*}
\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}\tag{1}\\
(1)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A == \ttgp{0}{0}.A}\tag{2}\\
(2)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A == \ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A}\tag{3}\\
\vdash\ConfReq{Self.[P]A}{Q}_\texttt{P}\tag{4}\\
(1),\,(4)\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A}{Q}\tag{5}\\
(2),\,(5)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.B == \ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.B}\tag{6}\\
(6)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.B == \ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}\tag{7}\\
(4)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B == \ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.B}\tag{8}\\
(8),\,(7)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B == \ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}\tag{9}
\end{gather*}
By Theorem~\ref{derivation to path swift}, we can transform this derivation into a rewrite path from $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}$ to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$, involving the initial rewrite rules only. We call this rewrite path $p^\prime$:
\begin{multline*}
p^\prime := (\ProtoConfInv{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}).\texttt{A}.\texttt{B} \circ \ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntro{P}{A}).\texttt{B}\\
\circ \ttgp{0}{0}.(\ProtoConfInv{\assocsym{P}{A}}{Q}).\texttt{B} \circ \ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.(\AssocIntro{Q}{B})
\end{multline*}
Unlike $p$, $p^\prime$ is \emph{not} a positive rewrite path, because the first and third steps are negative; each one applies a conformance rule backwards. We can visualize $p^\prime$ as a path in the rewrite graph, with the \index{negative rewrite step}negative rewrite steps going up:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}[column sep=small]
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]
&&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{B}\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend left]\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, bend left]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, bend left]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
We now have two \index{parallel rewrite paths}parallel rewrite paths: $p$ (from term reduction), and $p^\prime$ (constructed from our derivation). Their composition $p^\prime\circ p^{-1}$ is a rewrite loop; we can represent it as a diagram, with rules (*4) and (*6) indicated by dashed arrows:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}[column sep=small]
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]
&&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{B}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right]\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
Recall the pair of rewrite loops defined by the critical pairs of our rewrite system. We take the first rewrite loop, and \index{whiskering}whisker it on the right by \texttt{B}; then, we whisker the second rewrite loop on the left by \ttgp{0}{0}. Now, the two rewrite loops visit the common term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}$. Informally, we can ``glue'' them together at this point, and then we get $p^\prime\circ p^{-1}$.
In fact, given any two parallel rewrite paths in a \index{convergent rewrite system}convergent rewrite system, we can always ``tile'' the two-dimensional space between them if we take the finite set of rewrite loops generated by \index{resolving critical pair}resolving critical pairs, and glue them together along common edges or vertices after putting the loops ``in context'' via whiskering. We will develop this idea further in Chapter~\ref{rqm minimization}, but here is a thought to ruminate on in the meantime:
\begin{quote}
Terms, generated by a finite set of symbols, are the zero-dimensional objects in the rewrite graph. Rewrite paths, generated by a finite set of rewrite rules, define an equivalence relation on terms; they are the one-dimensional objects. Rewrite loops, generated by a finite set of critical pairs, define an equivalence relation on paths; they are the two-dimensional objects.
\end{quote}
An equivalence relation on paths is called a \emph{homotopy relation}.
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{overlap of first kind example}
Let's build on our previous example and look at how unbound type parameters reduce when they appear in requirements. We add a new protocol \texttt{R}, and declare a \index{constrained extension}constrained \index{protocol extension}protocol extension of \texttt{P} where \texttt{Self.A.B} conforms to \texttt{R}:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol R {}
protocol Q {
associatedtype B
}
protocol P {
associatedtype A: Q
}
extension P where Self.A.B: R {}
\end{Verbatim}
When type checking these declarations, we need to build a generic signature for this \index{protocol extension}protocol extension. We start with requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P}$ from the \index{extended type}extended type, and add the user-written requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}{R}$. The rewrite system looks like the previous example but with two new rules:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}}{R}\tag{7}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}}{R}\tag{8*}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Rule (7) corresponds to the user-written requirement. Rule (*8) is added by completion, resolving the overlap between rule (7) and (6) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}$:
\begin{align*}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
We record a rewrite loop defining rule (*8) via rule (4), (6) and (7):
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}).\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}"']\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[dd, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}).\protosym{R}"']&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}
\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\ProtoConfInv{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}}{R})"']
\\
&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}).\texttt{B}"']
\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, dashed, bend right, "(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}}{R})"']
&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B})"']&&
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Note that this was an overlap of the first kind, so rule (7) is now marked \index{left-simplified rule}\textbf{left-simplified}. Thus, rule (*8) completely supercedes rule (7). Rule (*8) survives minimization and maps to the requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P]A.[Q]B}{R}$, which appears in the generic signature that we output for this protocol extension:
\begin{quote}
\begin{verbatim}
<τ_0_0 where τ_0_0: P, τ_0_0.[P]A.[Q]B: R>
\end{verbatim}
\end{quote}
If our compiler invocation is generating a \index{serialized module}serialized module, we serialize the protocol extension's generic signature and do not compute it again when this module is imported in the future. We might still need a rewrite system for generic signature queries though, in which scenario we build a ``second-generation'' rewrite system:
\begin{enumerate}
\item We originally built a convergent rewrite system from the user-written requirements of the protocol extension.
\item After finding a minimal set of rules, we convert minimal rules to requirements, and serialize the resulting \index{generic signature}generic signature.
\item In a subsequent compiler invocation, we deserialize this generic signature.
\item Then, we build a convergent rewrite system from the requirements of this generic signature; rule (8) is now one of our initial rules.
\end{enumerate}
The rewrite system after step (1) is equivalent to that after step (4). That is, if we ignore \textbf{left-simplified} and \textbf{right-simplified} rules, both will have the same rules, up to permutation. (We can't completely prove this fact, because \index{requirement minimization}minimization is tricky. But this is the intended invariant here.)
\end{example}
\begin{example}
Now we're going to change \texttt{Q} to require that \texttt{B} conform to \texttt{R}. Intuitively, the conformance requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.B}{R}$ in the protocol extension's \texttt{where} clause is now redundant, because every \texttt{B} (of a type conforming to \texttt{Q}) now conforms to \texttt{R}:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol R {}
protocol Q {
associatedtype B: R
}
protocol P {
associatedtype A: Q
}
extension P where Self.A.B: R {}
\end{Verbatim}
The rewrite system for building the protocol extension's generic signature starts out as in the previous example, but now one more imported rule comes from protocol \texttt{Q}:
\[\ProtoConf{\assocsym{Q}{B}}{R}\]
The conformance rule $\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}}{R}$ overlaps with $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}$ on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}$, as before. This is an overlap of the first kind, so the original rule $\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}}{R}$ is marked \IndexDefinition{left-simplified rule}\textbf{left-simplified}. This time though, the critical pair is \index{trivial critical pair}trivial; both sides already reduce to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}$:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}).\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}"']\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[dd, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}).\protosym{R}"']&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}
\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\ProtoConfInv{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{B}}{R})"']
\\
&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}).\texttt{B}"']
\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}.\protosym{R}
\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, bend right, "\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.(\ProtoConf{\assocsym{Q}{B}}{R})"']
&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B})"']&&
\end{tikzcd}
\]
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{two protocols same assoc}
Our next goal is to understand what happens when a type parameter conforms to two unrelated protocols that both declare an associated type with the same name:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol P1 {
associatedtype A
}
protocol P2 {
associatedtype A
}
\end{Verbatim}
We're going to look at this generic signature:
\begin{quote}
\texttt{<\ttgp{0}{0} where \ttgp{0}{0}:~P1, \ttgp{0}{0}:~P2>}
\end{quote}
Every \index{equivalence class}equivalence class of type parameters can be uniquely identified by some \index{unbound type parameter}unbound type parameter. In the above, the type parameters \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A} and \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A} must therefore be equivalent to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}. We're going to see how this works out in the rewrite system. Here is the convergent rewrite system for the above generic signature:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\AssocIntro{P1}{A}\tag{1}&\\
\midrule
&\AssocIntro{P2}{A}\tag{2}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P1}\tag{3}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P2}\tag{4}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{*5}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{*6}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Rules (1) and (2) are imported from \texttt{P1} and \texttt{P2}, and rules (3) and (4) correspond to the conformance requirements $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P1}$ and $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P2}$. Completion also adds two additional rules. Rule (*5) is added when resolving the overlap between rule (3) and rule (1), exactly as in Example~\ref{assoc type completion example}.
Rule (4) overlaps with rule (2) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P2}.\texttt{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.&\protosym{P2}\\
&\protosym{P2}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
This gives us rule (*6), which has a new form we haven't seen before. One side of the critical pair reduces to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}$, and the other reduces to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}$ via rule (5).
We record a rewrite loop defining rule (*6) via (2), (4) and (5):
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P2}.\texttt{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntro{P2}{A})}%
{(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow \ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A})}%
{(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\Rightarrow \ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A})}%
{(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P2}}
\]
We can ``glue'' the rewrite loops defining rule (*5) and (*6) together into a single diagram:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P2}.\texttt{A}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right]&\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed]&&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\arrow[lu, Rightarrow, bend right]\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\arrow[ru, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed]\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right]&\\
&&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{P1}.\texttt{A}\arrow[uu, Rightarrow, bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\]
The two dashed arrows are rules (*5) and (*6). The solid arrows indicate a rewrite path joining $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}$ with $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}$ involving the initial rules only. This rewrite path corresponds to the following derivation:
\begin{gather*}
\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P1}\tag{1}\\
(1)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A == \ttgp{0}{0}.A}\tag{2}\\
\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P2}\tag{3}\\
(3)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A == \ttgp{0}{0}.A}\tag{4}\\
(4)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A} == \ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A}\tag{5}\\
(2),\,(5)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A == \ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A}\tag{6}
\end{gather*}
Indeed, we see that the equivalence class with reduced type \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A} contains three type parameters. Here they are with corresponding terms, in type parameter order. In this case, the reduced type and the reduced term coincide:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{ll}
\textbf{Type}&\textbf{Term}\\
\toprule
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}$\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}$\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}$
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
\end{example}
\section{More Critical Pairs}
\begin{example}\label{protocol inheritance completion example}
Consider this protocol inheritance hierarchy, where \texttt{Bot} inherits from \texttt{Mid}, which inherits from \texttt{Top}, and \texttt{Mid} declares an associated type:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol Top {}
protocol Mid: Top {
associatedtype A
}
protocol Bot: Mid {}
\end{Verbatim}
We're going to examine the rewrite system for the generic signature $G_\texttt{Bot}$, made up rules imported from \texttt{Mid} and \texttt{Bot}, and the local rules (as before, we omit the identity conformance rules):
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\AssocIntro{Mid}{A}\tag{1}&\\
&\ProtoInherit{Mid}{Top}\tag{2}&\\
\midrule
&\AssocIntro{Bot}{A}\tag{3}&\\
&\ProtoInherit{Bot}{Mid}\tag{4}&\\
&\protosym{Bot}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Bot}{A}\tag{*5}&\\
&\ProtoInherit{Bot}{Top}\tag{*6}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Bot}\tag{7}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Mid}\tag{*8}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Top}\tag{*9}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}\tag{*10}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}\tag{*11}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
We're going to focus on a handful of interesting rules:
\begin{itemize}
\item While \texttt{Bot} does declare any associated types, it inherits \texttt{A} from \texttt{Mid}; rule (3) is the \index{inherited associated type rule}inherited associated type introduction rule for \texttt{A}.
\item Rules (*5) and (*11) are added by completion as are a consequence of the inherited associated type introduction rule.
\item Rules (*6), (*8) and (*9) are also added by completion. They express the ``transitive'' conformance requirements $\ConfReq{Self}{Top}_\texttt{Bottom}$, $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Top}$ and $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Mid}$.
\end{itemize}
Rule (4) overlaps with rule (1) on the term $\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{Bot}.&\protosym{Mid}\\
&\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair records a rewrite loop defining rule (*5) via rule (1), (3) and (4):
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{Bot}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}}%
{\assocsym{Bot}{A}}%
{\protosym{Bot}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{Bot}.(\AssocIntro{Mid}{A})}%
{(\protosym{Bot}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Bot}{A})}%
{(\AssocIntroInv{Bot}{A})}%
{(\ProtoInheritInv{Bot}{Mid}).\texttt{A}}
\]
Rule (*5) says, if a \index{type-like term}type-like term conforming to \texttt{Bot} is followed by $\assocsym{Mid}{A}$, we can reduce it to $\assocsym{Bot}{A}$.
Rule (4) overlaps with rule (3) on the term $\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}.\protosym{Top}$:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{Bot}.&\protosym{Mid}\\
&\protosym{Mid}.\protosym{Top}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair records a rewrite loop defining rule (*6) via rule (2) and (4):
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}.\protosym{Top}}%
{\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Top}}%
{\protosym{Bot}}%
{\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}}%
{(\ProtoInherit{Bot}{Mid}).\protosym{Top}}%
{(\ProtoInherit{Bot}{Top})}%
{(\ProtoInheritInv{Bot}{Mid})}%
{\protosym{Bot}.(\ProtoInheritInv{Mid}{Top})}
\]
Rule (*6) says, if a type-like term conforms to \texttt{Bot}, it also conforms to \texttt{Top}. In general, after completion, rewrite rules of the form $\protosym{P}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{P}$ will encode the \index{transitive closure}transitive closure of the \index{inherited protocol}protocol inheritance relation.
This completes the rewrite system for \texttt{Bot}. Moving on to $G_\texttt{Bot}$, we see that rule (7) overlaps with rule (4) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}$:
\begin{align*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.&\protosym{Bot}\\
&\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair defines rule (*8) via rules (4), (7) and (*8):
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Bot}.\protosym{Mid}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Mid}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Bot}}%
{(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Bot}).\protosym{Mid}}%
{(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Mid})}%
{(\ProtoConfInv{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Bot})}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.(\ProtoInheritInv{Bot}{Mid})}
\]
Rule (*8) is the derived requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Mid}$. Rule (7) overlaps with rule (5) in the same way, defining rule (*9), which is the derived requirement $\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Top}$. Once again, we see the transitive closure of the protocol inheritance relation being computed.
Rule (7) overlaps with rule (3) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Bot}.\texttt{A}$, defining rule (*10), by the same general principle as in Example~\ref{assoc type completion example}.
Finally, rule (*8) overlaps with rule (1) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\ttgp{0}{0}.&\protosym{Mid}\\
&\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair defines rule (*11) via rule (1), (3) and (*8):
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{Mid}.\texttt{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntro{Mid}{A})}%
{(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A})}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntroInv{Bot}{A})}%
{(\ProtoConfInv{\ttgp{0}{0}}{Mid}).\texttt{A}}
\]
In this example, the relationship between \index{type parameter}type parameters and \index{type-like term}type-like terms is more subtle than we've previously seen, because the two distinct \index{associated type symbol}associated type symbols $\assocsym{Mid}{A}$ and $\assocsym{Bot}{A}$ both correspond to the same associated type \emph{declaration}. On one hand, the \index{equivalence class}equivalence class of \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Mid]A} contains one other type parameter, \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}. However, we have \emph{three} equivalent type-like terms: $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}$, $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}$, and $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}$. Not only that, but applying Algorithm~\ref{build term generic} to the \index{reduced type parameter}reduced type parameter \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Mid]A} outputs $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}$, which is \emph{not} a \index{reduced term}reduced term; the reduced term here is $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}$, because $\assocsym{Bot}{A}<\assocsym{Mid}{A}$ in the \index{reduction order!in requirement machine}reduction order (Algorithm~\ref{protocol reduction order}):
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{ll}
\textbf{Type}&\textbf{Term}\\
\toprule
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Mid]A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}$\\
&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}$\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}$
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Now, suppose we change the declaration of \texttt{Bot} to \emph{re-state} the associated type:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol Bot: Mid {
associatedtype A
}
\end{Verbatim}
The rewrite system is identical; we now call rule (3) an associated type introduction rule instead of an \emph{inherited} associated type introduction rule, but the rule remains the same. Our equivalence class has three type parameters and three terms, because now every associated type symbol corresponds to a declaration:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{ll}
\textbf{Type}&\textbf{Term}\\
\toprule
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Bot]A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}$\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Mid]A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Mid}{A}$\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}&$\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}$
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
We defined Algorithm~\ref{associated type order} of the type parameter order so that a \index{root associated type}root associated type declaration always precedes such a re-stated associated type declaration; therefore the reduced type parameter of our equivalence class remains \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[Mid]A}. The reduced term is also unchanged, $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{Bot}{A}$. This means that re-stating an associated type (or removing a re-stated associated type) does not change either the rewrite system or reduced type relation, and in particular, has no effect on calling convention, witness table layout, or any other aspect of the \index{ABI}ABI.
Note that because the correspondence is not immediate, the mapping of terms to type parameters must be defined in such a way to output a reduced type parameter given a reduced term, by a careful choice of associated type declaration at each step. This will be explained in Section~\ref{implqueries}. This minor complication could be avoided if it weren't for inherited associated type symbols, and the fact that the reduction order on associated type symbols differs from the type parameter order on associated type declarations. However, both of those behaviors have important redeeming qualities, as we will see in Section~\ref{recursive conformances redux}.
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{proto assoc rule}
We now ask if \texttt{f()} type checks; is \texttt{T.C.B} equivalent to \texttt{T.A}?
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol S {
associatedtype A
associatedtype B
associatedtype C: S where Self == Self.C.C, Self.B == Self.C.A
}
func f<T: S>(val: T.C.B) {
let val2: T.A = val
}
\end{Verbatim}
We're going to gain a better intuitive understanding of this protocol first. Here are two concrete conforming types:
\begin{Verbatim}
struct X: S {
typealias A = Int
typealias B = String
typealias C = Y
}
struct Y: S {
typealias A = String
typealias B = Int
typealias C = X
}
\end{Verbatim}
We can write down defining equations for the normal conformances $\ConfReq{X}{S}$ and $\ConfReq{Y}{S}$ in the \index{type substitution}type substitution algebra:
\begin{gather*}
\AssocType{[S]A} \otimes \ConfReq{X}{S} = \texttt{Int}\\
\AssocType{[S]B} \otimes \ConfReq{X}{S} = \texttt{String}\\
\AssocType{[S]C} \otimes \ConfReq{X}{S} = \texttt{Y}\\
\AssocConf{Self.[S]C}{S} \otimes \ConfReq{X}{S} = \ConfReq{Y}{S}\\[\medskipamount]
\AssocType{[S]A} \otimes \ConfReq{Y}{S} = \texttt{String}\\
\AssocType{[S]B} \otimes \ConfReq{Y}{S} = \texttt{Int}\\
\AssocType{[S]C} \otimes \ConfReq{Y}{S} = \texttt{X}\\
\AssocConf{Self.[S]C}{S} \otimes \ConfReq{Y}{S} = \ConfReq{X}{S}
\end{gather*}
Let $\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}$ be the \index{protocol substitution map}protocol substitution map for the conformance $\ConfReq{X}{S}$. A calculation shows that this conformance satisfies both same-type requirements $\FormalReq{Self == Self.C.C}$ and $\FormalReq{Self.B == Self.C.A}$ of \texttt{S}:
\begin{gather*}
\ttgp{0}{0}\otimes\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}=\texttt{X}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[S]C.[S]C}\otimes\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}=\AssocType{[S]C}\otimes\AssocConf{Self.[S]C}{S}\otimes\ConfReq{X}{S}=\texttt{X}\\[\medskipamount]
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[S]B}\otimes\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}=\AssocType{[S]B}\otimes\ConfReq{X}{S}=\texttt{String}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[S]C.[S]A}\otimes\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}=\AssocType{[S]A}\otimes\AssocConf{Self.[S]C}{S}\otimes\ConfReq{X}{S}=\texttt{String}
\end{gather*}
We see that applying $\Sigma_{\ConfReq{X}{S}}$ to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[S]A} and \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[S]C.[S]B} also outputs identical types: $\AssocType{[S]A}\otimes\ConfReq{X}{S}=\AssocType{[S]B}\otimes\ConfReq{Y}{S}=\texttt{Int}$. Is this the case for \emph{every} conformance to \texttt{S}? That is, is it true that $G_\texttt{S}\vDash\FormalReq{\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A} == \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}}$?
We will see the answer is ``yes,'' proving that our function \texttt{f()} type checks. For a visual perspective, we turn to the \index{type parameter graph}type parameter graph\footnote{In our previous formulation, the type parameter graph has a distinguished root node, with every generic parameter as a child of this root. Now, our generic signature only has one generic parameter, so a root node would be superflous; we omit it in what follows.} for $G_\texttt{S}$. Figure~\ref{protocol s fig} constructs this graph in three steps. Between each step, we have a \index{graph homomorphism}graph homomorphism---in fact, a \index{covering map}covering map, in the sense of Section~\ref{protocol component}---transforming one graph into the other:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The first step shows the graph as it would be without the protocol stating any same-type requirements; we get an infinite tree where each interior node is the parent of one other interior node, and two leaf nodes.
\item The second step introduces the requirement $\FormalReq{Self == Self.C.C}$, collapsing the infinite tree down to a finite graph with a cycle. Those type parameters with an even number of \texttt{C}'s are now equivalent to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}}, and those with an odd number, to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}.
\item The final step introduces $\FormalReq{Self.B == Self.C.A}$. This collapses \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.B} with \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.A}, and as one might suspect, \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A} with \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}.
\end{enumerate}
\begin{figure}\captionabove{Visualizing the type parameter graph of $G_\texttt{S}$ in three stages}\label{protocol s fig}
\begin{center}
\begin{tabular}{lc}
\toprule
(1) &
\begin{tikzpicture}
\node (T) [root] {\ttgp{0}{0}};
\node (TA) [interior, below left=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}};
\node (Dummy) [below=of T] {};
\node (TB) [interior, below right=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.B}};
\node (TC) [interior, below=of Dummy] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}};
\node (TCA) [interior, below left=of TC] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.A}};
\node (CDummy) [below=of TC] {};
\node (TCB) [interior, below right=of TC] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}};
\node (TCC) [interior, below=of CDummy] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C}};
\node (Rest) [interior, below=of TCC] {\vphantom{\texttt{P}}\ldots};
\begin{scope}[on background layer]
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TA.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (TC.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TB.north);
\path (TC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TCA.north);
\path (TC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (TCC.north);
\path (TC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TCB.north);
\path (TCC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (Rest.north);
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}\\
\midrule
(2) &
\begin{tikzpicture}
\node (T) [root] {\ttgp{0}{0}};
\node (TA) [interior, below left=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}};
\node (Dummy) [below=of T] {};
\node (TB) [interior, below right=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.B}};
\node (TC) [interior, below=of Dummy] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}};
\node (TCA) [interior, below left=of TC] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.A}};
\node (TCB) [interior, below right=of TC] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}};
\begin{scope}[on background layer]
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TA.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow, bend left] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (TC.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TB.north);
\path (TC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TCA.north);
\path (TC.north) edge [arrow, bend left] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (T.south);
\path (TC.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TCB.north);
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}\\
\midrule
(3)&
\begin{tikzpicture}
\node (T) [root] {\ttgp{0}{0}};
\node (TA) [interior, below left=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}};
\node (Dummy) [below=of T] {};
\node (TB) [interior, below right=of T] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.B}};
\node (TC) [interior, below=of Dummy] {\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}};
\begin{scope}[on background layer]
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TA.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow, bend left] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (TC.north);
\path (T.south) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TB.north);
\path (TC.north) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.A}}} (TB.south);
\path (TC.north) edge [arrow, bend left] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.C}}} (T.south);
\path (TC.north) edge [arrow] node [right] {\tiny{\texttt{.B}}} (TA.south);
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}\\
\bottomrule
\end{tabular}
\end{center}
\end{figure}
Indeed, a consequence of the two same-type requirements is that \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A} is equivalent to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.A}, which is equivalent to \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}. Here is the full derivation:
\begin{gather*}
\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}}{S}\tag{1}\\
\vdash\ConfReq{Self.C}{S}_\texttt{S}\tag{2}\\
(1),\,(2)\vdash\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}{S}\tag{3}\\
\vdash\FormalReq{Self.B == Self.C.A}_\texttt{S}\tag{4}\\
(3),\,(4)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B == \ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.A}\tag{5}\\
\vdash\FormalReq{Self == Self.C.C}_\texttt{S}\tag{6}\\
(1),\,(6)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0} == \ttgp{0}{0}.C.C}\tag{7}\\
(7)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C == \ttgp{0}{0}}\tag{8}\\
(1),\,(8)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.A == \ttgp{0}{0}.A}\tag{9}\\
(5),\,(9)\vdash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B == \ttgp{0}{0}.A}\tag{10}
\end{gather*}
We've collapsed our infinite tree down to only four infinite equivalence classes:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{l|l|l|l}
\toprule
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.B}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.C}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.A}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.C.C}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.A}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.C.C.C}&\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.C.C.B}\\
\ldots&\ldots&\ldots&\ldots\\
\bottomrule
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Now, let's look at our fundamental source of truth, the rewrite system. We start with an \index{identity conformance rule}identity conformance rule, three associated type introduction rules, and finally, three rules corresponding to user-written requirements:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoInherit{S}{S}\tag{1}&\\
&\AssocIntro{S}{A}\tag{2}&\\
&\AssocIntro{S}{B}\tag{3}&\\
&\AssocIntro{S}{C}\tag{4}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\protosym{S}.\texttt{C}}{S}\tag{5}&\\
&\protosym{S}.\texttt{C}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}.\texttt{B}\tag{6}&\\
&\protosym{S}.\texttt{C}.\texttt{C}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}\tag{7}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Completion also adds \emph{ten} new rules; we will reveal a few at a time. Let's consider the first rule, $\ProtoInherit{S}{S}$. Every protocol has an identity conformance rule, but in the previous examples it didn't play an important role so we ignored it. The identity conformance rule always overlaps with itself:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{S}.&\protosym{S}\\
&\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}
\end{align*}
The critical pair is always \index{trivial critical pair}trivial:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}\arrow[d, Rightarrow, "(\ProtoInherit{S}{S}).\protosym{S}"', bend right]\\
\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\protosym{S}.(\ProtoInheritInv{S}{S})"', bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Identity conformance rules also overlap with associated type introduction rules. For example, rule (1) overlaps with (2) on the term $\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}.\texttt{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{S}.&\protosym{S}\\
&\protosym{S}.\texttt{A}
\end{align*}
One side of this critical pair reduces to $\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}$, while the other reduces to $\assocsym{S}{A}$. We define a new rule $\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{A}$ and record a rewrite loop:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}}%
{\assocsym{S}{A}}%
{\protosym{S}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{S}.(\AssocIntro{S}{A})}%
{(\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{A})}%
{(\AssocIntroInv{S}{A})}%
{(\ProtoInheritInv{S}{S}).\texttt{A}}
\]
In the same way we get such a rule for every associated type:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{A}\tag{*8}&\\
&\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{B}\tag{*9}&\\
&\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{C}\tag{*10}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
While we could have also written down similar rules in previous examples, they would not have illustrated anything of consequence. They will shortly; but first, we have a few overlaps between conformance rules and associated type introduction rules. As in previous examples, we get the usual rules (*11), (*12), and (*13) for reducing unbound type parameters; we also left-simplify (5), (6) and (7), replacing them with rules (*14), (*15), and (*16):
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}\tag{*11}&\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{B}\tag{*12}&\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\texttt{C}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}\tag{*13}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{S}{C}}{S}\tag{*14}&\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}\tag{*15}&\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{B}\tag{*16}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Here is the main event: rule (*15) overlaps with (*16) on the term $\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}$:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{S}{C}.&\assocsym{S}{C}\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}
\end{align*}
The right-hand side of this critical pair reduces the overlap term $\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}$ with rule (*15), which gives us $\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}$. Previously, terms for bound type parameters would begin with \emph{either} a protocol symbol or an associated type symbol, but not both; the associated type symbol already encodes the protocol. Indeed, this funny-looking term reduces to just $\assocsym{S}{A}$ via rule (*8), defined as a consequence of that mysterious identity conformance rule (1).
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}}%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{B}}%
{\assocsym{S}{A}}%
{\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A}}%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.(\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{B})}%
{(\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{A})}%
{(\assocsym{S}{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}.\assocsym{S}{A})}%
{(\protosym{S}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}).\assocsym{S}{A}}
\]
At last, and as predicated, we get the rule that proves $G_\texttt{S}\vDash\FormalReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A == \ttgp{0}{0}.C.B}$:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{A}\tag{*17}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Now the \emph{encore}: rule (*15) overlaps with rule (*14) on the term $\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}.\protosym{S}$:
\begin{align*}
\assocsym{S}{C}.&\assocsym{S}{C}\\
&\assocsym{S}{C}.\protosym{S}
\end{align*}
This critical pair resolves \index{trivial critical pair}trivially, by way of the identity conformance rule:
\[
\FourLoopTrivial%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}.\protosym{S}}%
{\protosym{S}.\protosym{S}}%
{\protosym{S}}%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}}%
{(\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C}\Rightarrow\protosym{S}).\protosym{S}}%
{(\ProtoInherit{S}{S})}%
{(\protosym{S}\Rightarrow\assocsym{S}{C}.\assocsym{S}{C})}%
{\assocsym{S}{C}.(\ProtoConfInv{\assocsym{S}{C}}{S})}
\]
If the identity conformance rule had not been part of that initial set, this last critical pair would \emph{define} the identity conformance rule, and we would obtain the same rewrite system in the end. We don't need to explicitly add the identity conformance rule, after all. There is a practical consideration though. By making this rule part of the initial set, and cruicially, marking it \index{permanent rule}\textbf{permanent}, we remove it from consideration in the rewrite system minimization algorithm. This cuts out a lot of unnecessary work.
\smallskip
Protocol \texttt{S} is an interesting test case demonstrating the rewrite system's ability to discover non-trivial identities. It originates from a developer's bug report in 2020 \cite{sr12120}; \index{history}at the time, it broke the \Index{GenericSignatureBuilder@\texttt{GenericSignatureBuilder}}\texttt{GenericSignatureBuilder}'s minimization algorithm. Amusingly, the \index{Rust}Rust compiler's generics implementation is unable to prove the derived requirement:
\begin{Verbatim}
trait S {
type A;
type B;
type C: S<A = Self::B, C = Self>;
}
fn f<T: S>(val: <T::C as S>::B) {
let val2: T::A = val;
// note: expected associated type `<T as S>::A'
// found associated type `<<T as S>::C as S>::B'
}
\end{Verbatim}
\end{example}
\section{Tietze Transformations}\label{tietze transformations}
Both the \index{Knuth-Bendix algorithm}Knuth-Bendix completion and the \index{left simplification}rule simplification algorithms preserve the equivalence relation on terms. When completion adds a new rewrite rule, it is because the corresponding pair of terms are already joined by a \index{rewrite path}rewrite path. There is an analogous guarantee when \index{right simplification}rule simplification deletes a rewrite rule: the two terms are known to be joined by at least one other rewrite path that does not involve this rule. Intuitively, we understand that these transformations knead the \index{reduction relation}reduction relation into a better form, while the equivalence relation on terms remains completely determined by the relations of our initial \index{monoid presentation}monoid presentation.
Mathematically speaking, both algorithms are defined as a transformation on monoid presentations. This transformation decomposes into a composition of sequential steps, where at each step the monoid presentation is changed in such a way that \index{monoid isomorphism}monoid isomorphism is preserved. So far, we've seen two of the four isomorphism-preserving transformations below, so named after \index{Heinrich Tietze}Heinrich Tietze, who introduced them in 1908:
\begin{definition}
Let $\AR$ be a finitely-presented monoid. An \IndexDefinition{Tietze transformation}\emph{elementary Tietze transformation}, or just Tietze transformation, is one of the following:
\begin{enumerate}
\item (Adding a relation) If a pair of terms $u$, $v\in A^*$ are already joined by a rewrite path from $u$ to $v$---that is, if $u\sim v$ as elements of $\AR$---we can add $(u,\,v)$:
\[\langle A;\,R\cup\{(u,v)\}\rangle\]
\item (Removing a relation) If $(u,\,v)\in R$ and we have a rewrite path from $u$ to $v$ that does not contain the rewrite step $x(u\Rightarrow v)y$ or $x(v\Rightarrow u)y$ for any $x$, $y\in A^*$, we can remove $(u,v)$:
\[\langle A;\,R\setminus\{(u,v)\}\rangle\]
\item (Adding a symbol) If $a$ is some symbol distinct from all other symbols of $A$, and $t\in A^*$ is any term, we can simultaneously add $a$ and make it equivalent to $t$:
\[\langle A\cup\{a\};\,R\cup\{(t,a)\}\rangle\]
\item (Removing a symbol) If $a\in A$, $(t,a)\in R$ for some term $t$ not involving $a$, and no other $(u,v)\in R$ has a term $u$ or $v$ involving $a$, we can simultaneously remove $a$ and $(t,a)$:
\[\langle A\setminus\{a\};\,R\setminus\{(t,a)\}\rangle\]
\end{enumerate}
The following is the key result here: two finitely-presented monoids are isomorphic if and only if they are \emph{Tietze-equivalent}, meaning we can obtain one from the other by a finite sequence of elementary Tietze transformations.
\end{definition}
Some finer points:
\begin{itemize}
\item For every Tietze transformation, there is a complementary transformation which undoes the change; in this way (1) and (2) are inverses, and similarly (3) and (4).
\item We already know that changing the order of the terms in a relation---replacing $(u,v)\in R$ with $(v,u)$---does not change the set of rewrite steps generated, and thus presents the same monoid. Now we see this operation is actually a composition of two elementary Tietze transformations; we first add $(v,u)$, and remove $(u,v)$.
\item Some definitions of (4) drop the condition that the removed symbol $a$ not appear in any relation $(u,v)\in R$ other than the $(t,a)$ being simultaneously removed. Our restriction does not cost us any generality, because if $a$ occurs in any other relations, we can always first perform a series of Tietze transformations: for each such $(u,v)$, we replace occurrences of $a$ with $t$ in $u$ and $v$, add the new relation, and finally remove $(u,v)$. However, note that we must still require that $a$ must not occur in $t$.
\end{itemize}
\paragraph{Associated type symbols} Tietze transformations give us a new way to understand associated type symbols. The ultimate equivalence between rewrite systems built from user-written requirements and \index{requirement minimization}minimal requirements, shown in Section~\ref{critical pairs}, means we could have defined Algorithm \ref{build term generic}~and~\ref{build term protocol} to only ever build terms from \index{protocol symbol}protocol and \index{name symbol}name symbols. After completion, we end up with the same rewrite system, it just takes a little bit more work to get there. In this setup, among the initial rewrite rules, the only occurrences of \index{associated type symbol}associated type symbols are on the right-hand sides of \index{associated type introduction rule}associated type introduction rules:
\[\protosym{P}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}\]
Thus, we can understand the associated type introduction rules as having been added by a sequence of Tietze transformations of the third kind, applied to some monoid presentation. This ``primordial'' monoid presentation involves only protocol and name symbols, and it encodes the same monoid that ours does, up to isomorphism. So why do we bother with associated type symbols at all? In the next section, we will see the answer has to do with the interaction between recursive conformance requirements and completion.
\paragraph{Further discussion}
The elementary Tietze transformations are akin to rewrite steps, in that they define an edge relation on a ``rewrite graph'' whose vertices are monoid presentations. A ``rewrite path'' in this graph then witnesses the fact that the source and destination present the same monoid. The corresponding notion of word problem over this rewrite graph is the \index{monoid isomorphism problem}\emph{monoid isomorphism problem}. As expected, just as the \index{word problem}word problem is \index{undecidable problem}undecidable in general, so is the monoid isomorphism problem.
Tietze transformations are fundamental to the study of \emph{combinatorial group theory}, and are described in any book on the subject, such as \cite{combinatorialgroup}. Note that in a group presentation, a relation $(u, v)$ can always be written as $(uv^{-1},\varepsilon)$, with the identity element on the right hand side. The term $uv^{-1}$ is called a \emph{relator}; a set of relators takes the place of relations in a group presentation. Tietze transformations of monoid presentations are described in \cite{book2012string} and \cite{henry2021tietze}.
\section{Recursive Conformances}\label{recursive conformances redux}
From previous examples, it may look like completion essentially enumerates \emph{all} derived requirements, but this cannot be true in general. We know from Section~\ref{recursive conformances} that \index{recursive conformance requirement}recursive conformance requirements give us generic signatures with an infinite set of \index{derived requirement}derived requirements. If the compiler is to allow such generic signatures, this infinite set of derived requirements must be encoded by a finite number of rewrite rulese.
We will see that with recursive conformance requirements, successful termination of the Knuth-Bendix algorithm depends both on the existence of associated type symbols (and introduction rules), and our choice of reduction order. This furnishes the concrete example for a scenario mentioned in Section~\ref{word problem}.
\begin{example}
Our first example is the protocol \texttt{N} that we encountered several times already, most recently in Section~\ref{monoidsasprotocols}:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol N {
associatedtype A: N
}
\end{Verbatim}
Let's look at the convergent rewrite system for $G_\texttt{N}$:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoInherit{N}{N}\tag{1}&\\
&\AssocIntro{N}{A}\tag{2}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}{N}\tag{3}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{N}{A}}{N}\tag{*4}\\
&\protosym{N}.\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}\tag{*5}&\\
&\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\tag{*6}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{N}\tag{7}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}\tag{*8}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Rules (*4), (*5), (*6) and (*8) are defined by the rewrite loops shown in Figure~\ref{recursive n loops}. Rule~(3) is marked \textbf{left-simplified} because its left-hand side $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$ can always be reduced by the rewrite path $(\AssocIntro{N}{A}).\protosym{N}\circ(\ProtoConf{\assocsym{N}{A}}{N})$.
\begin{figure}\captionabove{Critical pairs in $G_\texttt{N}$}\label{recursive n loops}
\begin{center}
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}}%
{\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{N}}%
{\assocsym{N}{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}).\protosym{N}}%
{(\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A})}%
{(\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A})}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N})}
\bigskip
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{N}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.\assocsym{N}{A}}%
{\assocsym{N}{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.(\AssocIntro{N}{A})}%
{(\protosym{N}.\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A})}%
{(\AssocIntroInv{N}{A})}%
{(\ProtoInheritInv{N}{N}).\texttt{A}}
\bigskip
\begin{tikzcd}
&\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(\ProtoConf{\assocsym{N}{A}}{N}).\texttt{A}"', bend right]\\
\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, "(\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A})"', bend right, dashed]&&
\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\arrow[ul, Rightarrow, "\assocsym{N}{A}.(\AssocIntroInv{N}{A})"', bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\bigskip
\begin{tikzcd}
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, "(\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{N}).\texttt{A}"', bend right]\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\arrow[rr, Rightarrow, "(\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A})"', bend right, dashed]&&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}\arrow[ul, Rightarrow, "\ttgp{0}{0}.(\AssocIntroInv{N}{A})"', bend right]
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{figure}
In our rewrite system, the valid \index{type-like term}type-like terms have \ttgp{0}{0} as the first symbol, and either \texttt{A} or $\assocsym{N}{A}$ as each subsequent symbol. Any type-like term reduces to a term of the same length:
\[\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\rightarrow \ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\]
The reduced terms are those that do not contain \texttt{A}; that is, a reduced term has the form $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}^n$. Also, every type parameter of $G_\texttt{N}$ conforms to \texttt{N}. We have two infinite families of derived conformance requirements, where the subject types are the bound and unbound type parameters from each equivalence class:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{l}
\toprule
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A}{N}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A.[N]A}{N}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A.[N]A.[N]A}{N}\\
\ldots\\
\midrule
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}{N}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A}{N}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A.A}{N}\\
\ldots\\
\bottomrule
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Each derived requirement corresponds to an equivalence of terms $t.\protosym{N}\sim t$, where $t$ is a type-like term. We can explicitly construct rewrite paths that witness these equivalences. Let's temporarily denote the positive rewrite step for rules (*4), (*6) and (*8) by $\alpha$, $\beta$ and $\gamma$ respectively:
\begin{gather*}
\alpha := (\ProtoConf{\assocsym{N}{A}}{N})\\
\beta := (\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A})\\
\gamma := (\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A})
\end{gather*}
For a derived requirement with bound subject type, $t=\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}^n$. We can rewrite $t.\protosym{N}$ to $t$ with a single rewrite step, using rule $\alpha$ to eliminate the suffix $\protosym{N}$ while leaving the rest of the term unchanged:
\begin{gather*}
\ttgp{0}{0}\star\alpha\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}\star\alpha\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\star\alpha\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
For those derived requirements with unbound subject types, $t=\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}$. To rewrite $t.\protosym{N}$ to $t$, we first reduce $t\rightarrow t^\prime$, eliminate $\protosym{N}$ with rule $\alpha$, and reverse the reduction to obtain~$t$. The reduction is given by a path $p_n$, where each $p_n$ rewrites $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}^n\rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}^n$:
\begin{gather*}
p_1:=\gamma\\
p_2:=(\gamma\star\texttt{A}.\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}\star\beta\star\protosym{N})\\
p_3:=(\gamma\star\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}\star\beta\star\texttt{A}.\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}\star\beta\star\protosym{N})\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
Thus, the derived requirements with unbound subject types correspond to the following rewrite paths:
\begin{gather*}
(p_1\star\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}\star\alpha)\circ p_1^{-1}\\
(p_2\star\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}\star\alpha)\circ p_2^{-1}\\
(p_3\star\protosym{N})\circ(\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\star\alpha)\circ p_3^{-1}\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
For example, $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$ and $\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}$ both reduce to $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}$; we can join them with this rewrite path:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}
\arrow[d, Rightarrow, "\gamma"']&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}
\arrow[d, Rightarrow, "\beta"']&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\gamma^{-1}"']\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}
\arrow[d, Rightarrow, "\beta"']&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\beta^{-1}"']\\
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{N}
\arrow[r, Rightarrow, "\alpha"', bend right]&
\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}
\arrow[u, Rightarrow, "\beta^{-1}"']
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Thus, our eight rules encode two infinite families of derived requirements.
\smallskip
Now, we will show that the associated type introduction rule $\AssocIntro{N}{A}$ was essential. Let's start over with our the initial rules, but delete the symbol $\assocsym{N}{A}$ and rule~(2) before attempting completion. Only two rules remain:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoInherit{N}{N}&\tag{1}\\
&\ProtoConf{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}{N}&\tag{3}\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
We see that rule (3) rule overlaps with itself on the term $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.&\protosym{N}\\
&\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}
\end{align*}
Resolving this critical pair introduces a new rule $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}).\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A})}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}).\texttt{A}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N})}
\]
After adding this rule, we check for overlaps again. The new rule overlaps with rule~(3) on $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$, and also with itself on $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$. Rule~(3) also overlaps with the new rule on $\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}$. It is apparent that resolving those critical pairs will introduce new rules, and this process will never end. We get an infinite family of critical pairs, indexed by $m$, $n\in\mathbb{N}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^n.\protosym{N}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^{m+n}.\protosym{N}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^{m+n}}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^n}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m).\texttt{A}^n.\protosym{N}}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^{m+n}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^{m+n})}%
{(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m.\protosym{N}).\texttt{A}^n}%
{\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^m.(\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^n\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}^n.\protosym{N})}
\]
These critical pairs define an infinite sequence of rewrite rules:
\begin{gather*}
\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
Adding the symbol $\assocsym{N}{A}$ together with the rule $\AssocIntro{N}{A}$ is a \index{Tietze transformation}Tietze transformation, so we know it does not change the equivalence relation on terms. However, it makes our rewrite system convergent. Convergence also depends on associated type symbols preceding name symbols, so $\assocsym{N}{A}<\texttt{A}$. Otherwise, we once again end up with an infinite sequence of rewrite rules:
\begin{gather*}
\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}.\texttt{A}\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
Let's summarize this example using \index{monoid presentation}monoid presentations and \index{Tietze transformation}Tietze transformations. We write $n$, $a$, $b$ instead of $\protosym{N}$, \texttt{A}, $\assocsym{N}{A}$. Together with the identity conformance rule, the user-written requirement $\ConfReq{Self.A}{N}_\texttt{N}$, with an unbound type parameter as the subject type, defines this presentation over the alphabet $a$, $n$:
\[M_1 := \langle a,\,n;\,nn\sim n,\,nan\sim na\rangle\]
We saw that completion does not terminate on $M_1$; abstractly, we can understand it as producing an \IndexDefinition{infinite convergent presentation}\emph{infinite} convergent presentation $M_1^\prime$, containing a family of rewrite rules parameterized by $i\in\mathbb{N}$:
\[M_1^\prime := \langle a,\,n;\,na^in\sim na^i\rangle\]
To fix completion, we added the symbol $b$ with defining relation $na\sim b$ to $M_1$; a Tietze transformation which gave us the presentation $M_2$ over $a$, $b$, $n$:
\[M_2 := \langle a,\,b,\,n;\,nn\sim n,\,nan\sim na,\,na\sim b\rangle\]
Performing completion on $M_2$ with the reduction order $n<b<a$ succeeds after adding the two relations $bn\sim b$ and $ba\sim bb$, giving us the finite convergent presentation $M_2^\prime$:
\[M_2^\prime := \langle a,\,b,\,n;\,nn\sim n,\,nan\sim na,\,na\sim b,\,bn\sim b,\,ba\sim bb\rangle\]
Rule simplification removes the relation $nan\sim na$, giving us a reduced presentation:
\[M_2^{\prime\prime} := \langle a,\,b,\,n;\,nn\sim n,\,na\sim b,\,bn\sim b,\,ba\sim bb\rangle\]
We haven't seen \index{requirement minimization}rewrite system minimization yet, but to minimize $M_2^{\prime\prime}$, we eliminate all relations added by completion except for $bn\sim b$, which we need because the original relation $nan\sim na$ was deleted. This leaves us with $M_3$:
\[M_3:=\langle a,\,b,\,n;\,nn\sim n,\,na\sim b,\,bn\sim b\rangle\]
The rule $bn\sim b$ is the minimal conformance requirement $\ConfReq{Self.[N]A}{N}_\texttt{N}$ with a bound type parameter as the subject type. All of the above presentations define the \emph{same} monoid, up to isomorphism. Furthermore, if we perform completion on $M_3$, we get $M_2^{\prime\prime}$.
\end{example}
\begin{example}
Let's say we inherit from \texttt{N}, and impose our own recursive conformance requirement on \texttt{A}:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol Q: N where A: Q {}
\end{Verbatim}
Even though protocol \texttt{Q} does not declare an associated type named \texttt{A}, we define an associated type symbol $\assocsym{Q}{A}$ and corresponding introduction rule $\AssocIntro{Q}{A}$. We will see that convergence is contingent on this rule.
The generic signature $G_\texttt{Q}$ has all the derived requirements of $G_\texttt{N}$, and adds two more infinite families of conformances to \texttt{Q}:
\begin{quote}
\begin{tabular}{l}
\toprule
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A}{Q}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A.[N]A}{Q}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.[N]A.[N]A.[N]A}{Q}\\
\ldots\\
\midrule
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}{Q}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A}{Q}\\
\ConfReq{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A.A}{Q}\\
\ldots\\
\bottomrule
\end{tabular}
\end{quote}
Listing~\ref{rewrite system q} shows the convegent rewrite system for \texttt{Q}, which imports rules from protocol~\texttt{N}. Completion discovers the following critical pairs; we will be content to just summarize because they are similar to previous examples:
\begin{itemize}
\item Rule (6) overlaps with (7) on $\protosym{Q}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}$. We define rule (*10) (this general principle was established in Example~\ref{proto assoc rule}).
\item Rule (8) overlaps with (2) on $\protosym{Q}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}$. We define rule (*11) (Example~\ref{protocol inheritance completion example}).
\item Rule (9) overlaps with (7) on $\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{Q}$. We define rule (*12), and mark rule (9) as \index{left-simplified rule}\textbf{left-simplified} (Example~\ref{overlap of first kind example}).
\item Rule (*12) overlaps with (8) on $\assocsym{Q}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\protosym{N}$. We define rule (*13).
\item Rule (*12) overlaps with (7) on $\assocsym{Q}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}$. We define rule (*14) (Example~\ref{assoc type completion example}).
\item Rule (*13) overlaps with (2) on $\assocsym{Q}{A}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}$. We define rule (*15).
\end{itemize}
\begin{listing}\captionabove{Rewrite system for protocol \texttt{Q}}\label{rewrite system q}
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoInherit{N}{N}\tag{1}&\\
&\AssocIntro{N}{A}\tag{2}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{N}{A}}{N}\tag{3}\\
&\protosym{N}.\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}\tag{*4}&\\
&\assocsym{N}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\tag{*5}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoInherit{Q}{Q}\tag{6}&\\
&\AssocIntro{Q}{A}\tag{7}&\\
&\ProtoInherit{Q}{N}\tag{8}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}}{Q}\tag{9}&\\
&\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{Q}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Q}{A}\tag{*10}\\
&\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Q}{A}\tag{*11}\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{Q}{A}}{Q}\tag{*12}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{Q}{A}}{N}\tag{*13}&\\
&\assocsym{Q}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Q}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{A}\tag{*14}\\
&\assocsym{Q}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{Q}{A}.\assocsym{Q}{A}\tag{*15}\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
\end{listing}
Here's a question. What if we only had associated type symbols that directly correspond to associated type declarations? That is, what if we got rid of the symbol $\assocsym{Q}{A}$, together with rule (7), the inherited associated type introduction rule $\AssocIntro{Q}{A}$? The resulting monoid would again be equivalent, because this is a \index{Tietze transformation}Tietze transformation. However, we will see that completion fails.
Rule (8) still overlaps with rule (2), but instead of rule (*11), we now get a rule $\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}$ when we resolve this critical pair:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
&\protosym{Q}.\protosym{N}.\texttt{A}\arrow[ld, Rightarrow, bend right, "(\protosym{Q}.\protosym{N}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}).\texttt{A}"']\\
\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\arrow[rd, Rightarrow, bend right, dashed, "(\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A})"']&\\
&\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}\arrow[uu, Rightarrow, bend right, "\protosym{Q}.(\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{N}.\texttt{A})"']
\end{tikzcd}
\]
Rule (9) now overlaps with $\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}$. We get a new rule $\ProtoConf{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}}{Q}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{Q}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}}%
{(\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}).\protosym{Q}}%
{(\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A})}%
{\protosym{Q}.(\assocsym{N}{A}\Rightarrow\texttt{A})}%
{(\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\texttt{A}.\protosym{Q})}
\]
Now, the rule $\ProtoConf{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}}{Q}$ overlaps with itself on the term $\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}$:
\begin{align*}
\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.&\protosym{Q}\\
&\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}
\end{align*}
The overlaps of this rule with itself generate an infinite family of critical pairs indexed by $m$,~$n\in\mathbb{N}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^m.\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^n.\protosym{Q}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^{m+n}.\protosym{Q}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^{m+n}}%
{\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^m.\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^n}%
{}%
{(\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^{m+n}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}^{m+n})}%
{}%
{}
\]
These critical pairs define an infinite family of rewrite rules:
\begin{gather*}
\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}\\
\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\\
\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\protosym{Q}\Rightarrow\protosym{Q}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}.\assocsym{N}{A}\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
Recall that the \index{protocol reduction order}reduction order on protocols was defined to compare the number of elements in the \index{protocol inheritance closure}protocol inheritance closure before comparing names. So if neither \texttt{N} nor \texttt{Q} inherited any other protocols, we would have $\protosym{N}<\protosym{Q}$. However, since \texttt{Q} inherits from \texttt{N}, we have $\protosym{Q}<\protosym{N}$ and thus $\assocsym{Q}{A}<\assocsym{N}{A}$. We won't go into details, but the convergence of the above rewrite system \emph{also} depends on the reduction order being so. If instead $\assocsym{N}{A}<\assocsym{Q}{A}$, our rewrite system would not have a (finite) convergent presentation (we will see below that we can still describe an \emph{infinite} convergent presentation; but we have no way to compute with one).
\smallskip
To summarize the theory, let's write $a$, $b$, $c$, $p$, $q$ instead of \texttt{A}, $\assocsym{N}{A}$, $\assocsym{Q}{A}$, $\protosym{P}$, $\protosym{Q}$. The identity conformance rules and user-written requirements of \texttt{N} and \texttt{Q} define the following presentation:
\[M_1 := \langle a,n,q;\,nn\sim n,\, nq\sim n,\, qq\sim q,\,nan\sim na,\,qaq\sim qa\rangle\]
Completion doesn't terminate with the above; abstractly, we get an \index{infinite convergent presentation}infinite convergent presentation over the same generators:
\[M_1^\prime := \langle a,n,q;\,na^in\sim na^i,\, qa^in\sim qa^i,\,qa^iq\sim qa^i\rangle\]
The first Tietze transformation adds $b$ with defining relation $na\sim b$, as in the previous example:
\[M_2 := \langle a,b,n,q;\,nn\sim n,\, qq\sim q,\, qn\sim q,\, nan\sim na,\,qaq\sim qa,\,na\sim b\rangle\]
We saw that completion still fails; we get the following \index{infinite convergent presentation}infinite convergent presentation:
\[M_2^{\prime} := \langle a,b,n,q;\,nn\sim n,\,na\sim b,\,bn\sim b,\,ba\sim bb,\,qb^iq\sim qb^i,\, qb^ia\sim qb^{i+1}\rangle\]
However, we then add $c$ with defining relation $qa\sim c$:
\[M_3 := \langle a,b,c,n,q;\,nn\sim n,\, qq\sim q,\, qn\sim q,\, nan\sim na,\,qaq\sim qa,\,na\sim b,\,qa\sim c\rangle\]
Completion suceeds on $M_3$ using a reduction order where $c<b<a$ and $p<n$, and we get a finite convergent rewrite system. We've already listed the numerous rules once, so we won't do it again. Let's call this finite convergent presentation $M_2^\prime$:
\[M_3^\prime := \langle a,b,c,n,q;\,\mbox{\ldots 15 relations \ldots}\rangle\]
The minimized rewrite system corresponds to this presentation:
\[M_4 :=\langle a,b,c,n,q;\,nn\sim n,\, na\sim b,\, bn\sim b,\, qq\sim q,\, qa\sim c,\, qn\sim q,\, cq\sim c\rangle\]
If we start with $M_3$ and perform completion, we again get $M_2^\prime$.
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{merged assoc type example}
Our final example lays bare a \index{limitation}limitation of the Requirement Machine in the form a generic signature whose rewrite system is not convergent. It is probably the simplest possible such instance, so we will study it in detail. We will attempt to combine the recursion of protocol \texttt{N}, with an equivalence between two associated types that have the same name in unrelated protocols, as in Example~\ref{two protocols same assoc}. The setup is the same as in that example, but now both associated types are subject to recursive conformance requirements:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol P1 {
associatedtype A: P1
}
protocol P2 {
associatedtype A: P2
}
\end{Verbatim}
We define a type parameter conforming to both \texttt{P1} and \texttt{P2}:
\begin{quote}
\texttt{<\ttgp{0}{0} where \ttgp{0}{0}:~P1, \ttgp{0}{0}:~P2>}
\end{quote}
We have the following initial rewrite rules:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoInherit{P1}{P1}\tag{1}&\\
&\AssocIntro{P1}{A}\tag{2}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P1}{A}}{P1}\tag{3}&\\
&\assocsym{P1}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{4}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoInherit{P2}{P2}\tag{5}&\\
&\AssocIntro{P2}{A}\tag{6}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P2}{A}}{P2}\tag{7}&\\
&\assocsym{P2}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P2}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\tag{8}&\\
\midrule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P1}\tag{9}&\\
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}}{P2}\tag{10}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
In our generic signature, there are infinitely many type parameters, all of the form \ttgp{0}{0} followed by a combination of \texttt{A}, \texttt{[P1]A} and \texttt{[P2]A}:
\begin{gather*}
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A.[P1]A}\\
\texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A.A.[P2]A}\\
\ldots
\end{gather*}
Membership in an equivalence class is determined by the number of \texttt{A}'s appearing in the type parameter, so \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P1]A.[P1]A}, \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.A.A} and \texttt{\ttgp{0}{0}.[P2]A.[P2]A} are all equivalent, so we can derive same-type requirements for these equivalences.
Rules (9) and (10) overlap with (2) and (6), respectively. Resolving these overlaps proceeds as in Example~\ref{two protocols same assoc}:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{11}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{12}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
We added new rules, so we must check for overlapping rules again. Now, (12) overlaps with (7) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\protosym{P2}$, and rule (12) also overlaps with (8) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\texttt{A}$. Resolving both critical pairs adds two new rules:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}}{P2}\tag{13}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{14}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
We now begin the third round, with another two critical pairs: rule (14) overlaps with (7) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\protosym{P2}$, and with (8) on the term $\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\texttt{A}$.
A pattern begins to emerge. We add two new rules, but we have two new critical pairs:
\begin{flalign*}
\toprule
&\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}}{P2}\tag{15}&\\
&\ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow \ttgp{0}{0}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}.\assocsym{P1}{A}\tag{16}&\\
\bottomrule
\end{flalign*}
Completion eventually hits a limit and fails. Our rewrite system actually has two infinite families of critical pairs; the first family defines a rule $\ProtoConf{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n}{P2}$ for each $n\in\mathbb{N}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^{n-1}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\protosym{P2}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n.\protosym{P2}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^{n-1}.\assocsym{P2}{A}}%
{}%
{}%
{}%
{}
\]
The second defines $\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n.\assocsym{P2}{A}\Rightarrow \ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^{n+1}$:
\[
\FourLoopDerived%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^{n-1}.\assocsym{P2}{A}.\texttt{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n.\assocsym{P2}{A}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^{n+1}}%
{\ttgp{0}{0}.{\assocsym{P1}{A}}^n.\texttt{A}}%
{}%
{}%
{}%
{}
\]
With protocol \texttt{N}, associated type introduction rules allowed us to use a finite set of rewrite rules to describe an infinite set of derived requirements. In the next example of protocol \texttt{Q} inheriting from \texttt{N}, inherited associated type rules saved the day. This time though, associated type we don't have any more tricks left up our sleeve.
\smallskip
Let's write $a$, $b$, $c$, $p$, $q$, $t$ instead of $\texttt{A}$, $\assocsym{P}{A}$, $\assocsym{Q}{A}$, $\protosym{P}$, $\protosym{Q}$, $\ttgp{0}{0}$. Our generic signature defines the following monoid presentation over the alphabet $a$, $p$, $q$, $t$:
\[M_1 := \langle a,p,q,t;\,pp\sim p,\,pap\sim pa,\,qq\sim q,\, qaq\sim qa,\, tp\sim t,\, tq\sim t\rangle\]
The Requirement Machine added the symbols $b$ and $c$ with defining relations $pa\sim b$ and $qa\sim c$, respectively:
\begin{align*}
M_2 := \langle a,b,c,p,q,t;\,\hbox{}&pp\sim p,\,pap\sim pa,\,qq\sim q,\, qaq\sim qa,\\
&tp\sim t,\, tq\sim t,\,pa\sim b,\,qa\sim c\rangle
\end{align*}
We saw that completion fails; we got an \index{infinite convergent presentation}infinite convergent presentation over the same alphabet:
\begin{align*}
M_2^\prime := \langle a,b,c,p,q,t;\,\hbox{}&pp\sim p,\,pa\sim b,\,bp\sim b,\,ba\sim bb,\\
&qq\sim q,\,qa\sim c,\,cq\sim c,\,ca\sim cc,\\
&ta\sim tb,\, tb^iq\sim tb^i,\,tb^ic\sim tb^{i+1}\rangle
\end{align*}
In fact, the associated type introduction rules don't simplify our understanding of this monoid at all. We can also write down an infinite convergent presentation for the completion of $M_1$:
\[M_1^\prime := \langle a,p,q,t;\,pa^ip\sim pa^i,\, qa^iq\sim qa^i,\, ta^ip\sim ta^i,\, ta^iq\sim ta^i\rangle\]
This infinite presentation is simple enough that one can implement a one-off algorithm for solving the word problem in $M_1^\prime$. We can simplify the original monoid presentation further by removing $pp\sim p$ and $qq\sim q$; the result is \emph{not} Tietze-equivalent, but it runs into the same problems with completion.
\paragraph{Future directions.} We will now state an open question about this strikingly simple monoid presentation of only four symbols and relations:
\begin{quote}
Can the monoid $\langle a,p,q,t;\,pap\sim pa,\, qaq\sim qa,\, tp\sim t,\, tq\sim t\rangle$ be presented by a finite convergent rewrite system?
\end{quote}
Either of the possible outcomes would be of interest:
\begin{itemize}
\item If we can answer in the affirmative, then the Requirement Machine might be able to support our generic signature by tweaking how we construct the symbols and rules of our rewrite system.
\item If instead we prove that no such convergent rewrite system exists, we have another example of a finitely-presented monoid with decidable word problem that cannot be presented by a finite convergent rewrite system, much like Theorem~\ref{squier s1}.
\end{itemize}
One approach to the study of \index{infinite convergent presentation}infinite convergent rewrite systems is via formal language theory; this is explored in~\cite{OTTO1998621}. We recall the standard definitions, which can be found in \cite{formalmans1}. A \index{language}\emph{language} over an alphabet $A$ is a subset of the free monoid $A^*$; a language is \index{recursive language}\emph{recursive} if there is a total computable function to determine membership in this set, and a \index{regular language}\emph{regular language} is a set of strings recognized by a finite state automaton (or equivalently, matching a regular expression---the classical kind, without back references). The left-hand sides of the rules in a (finite or infinite) convergent rewrite system define a language in this sense, and a finite convergent rewrite system is then the special case where this language is finite; this direction is explored in.
Every finitely-presented monoid can be presented by an infinite convergent rewrite system; but if the word problem in this monoid is undecidable, the rewrite system's language is not recursive, so of course this viewpoint does not fundamentally change the difficulty of the problem. However, if we consider infinite convergent presentations with a sufficiently restricted class of language (for instance, regular languages), we can find an effective procedure for term reduction with a rewrite system of this type. Completion then becomes a highly non-trivial problem. A completion procedure for a certain kind of infinite convergent rewrite system was proposed in \cite{NEEDHAM1996195}; there, the left-hand sides involve exponents, much like the notation $ta^ip\sim ta^i$ and $ta^iq\sim ta^i$ used in our examples here. In principle, such an extension could one day be considered for the Requirement Machine.
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{double encoding}
We end this chapter with one final curiosity. We proved the derived requirements formalism to be undecidable in Section~\ref{monoidsasprotocols} by showing that an arbitrary finitely-presented monoid $\AR$ can be encoded in the form of a protocol declaration. In Chapter~\ref{symbols terms rules} we defined a lowering of a generic signature and its protocol dependencies into a finitely-presented monoid. If we chain both transformations, we see that we can map a finitely-presented monoid to a protocol declaration and then back to a finitely-presented monoid. In what sense does the latter monoid encode the original monoid?
Let $A^*:=\{a,b,c\}$, $R:=\{(ab,c),\,(bc,\varepsilon)\}$, and consider the monoid $M:=\AR$. Written down as a Swift protocol, $M := \langle a,\,b,\,c;\,ab\sim c,\,bc\sim\varepsilon\rangle$ looks like this:
\begin{Verbatim}
protocol P {
associatedtype A: P
associatedtype B: P
associatedtype C: P
where A.B == C, B.C == Self
}
\end{Verbatim}
Now we pretend to comment out the \texttt{where} clause, so now our protocol \texttt{P} just presents the free monoid $A^*$. We will list the convergent rewrite system for \texttt{P}, but partition the rules into two sets in a new way. The first set of rules involves name symbols; we call this set $\mathcal{N}$:
\begin{gather*}
\AssocIntro{P}{A}\\
\AssocIntro{P}{B}\\
\AssocIntro{P}{C}\\
\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}\\
\assocsym{P}{A}.\texttt{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{C}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{B}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\texttt{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{C}\\
\assocsym{P}{C}.\texttt{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\assocsym{P}{C}.\texttt{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{B}\\
\assocsym{P}{C}.\texttt{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{C}
\end{gather*}
The second set involves protocol and associated type symbols only. We call this set $\mathcal{S}$:
\begin{gather*}
\ProtoInherit{P}{P}\\
\protosym{P}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\protosym{P}.\assocsym{P}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{B}\\
\protosym{P}.\assocsym{P}{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}\\
\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{A}}{P}\\
\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{B}}{P}\\
\ProtoConf{\assocsym{P}{C}}{P}
\end{gather*}
The union $\mathcal{N}\cup\mathcal{S}$ is a rewrite system for a protocol encoding the free monoid $\{a,b,c\}^*$. Here, $\mathcal{N}$ contains 12 elements, and $\mathcal{S}$ contains 7 elements. More generally, if $|A|=n$, we have $|\mathcal{N}|=n(n+1)$ and $|\mathcal{S}|=2n+1$. Now, if we identify $a$, $b$, $c$ with $\assocsym{P}{A}$, $\assocsym{P}{B}$, $\assocsym{P}{C}$, and define a new symbol $e:=\protosym{P}$, we see that $\langle A\cup\{e\};\,\mathcal{S}\rangle$ is a convergent presentation. But to understand the object it presents, we need a few related definitions.
A \IndexDefinition{semigroup}\emph{semigroup} is a set together with an associative binary operation, but without a distinguished identity element. The \IndexDefinition{free semigroup}\emph{free semigroup} over a set $A$, denoted $A^+$, is the set of all \emph{non-empty} strings from the symbols of $A$. We can define a \IndexDefinition{finitely-presented semigroup}\emph{finitely-presented semigroup} analogously to a finitely-presented monoid; here the relations have the form $(u,v)$ where $u$, $v\in A^+$.
Every monoid trivially satisfies the semigroup axioms, and thus a free monoid $A^*$ is also a semigroup. However a free monoid $A^*$ is not a \emph{free} semigroup. For example, taking $A:=\{a,b,c\}$, we see among the elements of $A^*$ \emph{viewed as a semigroup}, we have non-trivial identities involving $\varepsilon$, such as $a=\varepsilon a$, $b\varepsilon=b$, and so on. Thus, this cannot be a free semigroup, where $xy\neq x$ and $xy\neq y$ for all $x$, $y\in A^+$. The free monoid $A^*$ \emph{is} a finitely-presented semigroup though; we must add the symbol $e$ to the alphabet, and a pair of relations $ex=e$, $xe=e$ for each $x\in A$. For example, as a semigroup, $\{a,b,c\}^*$ has four generators and seven relations:
\[\langle a,\,b,\,c,\,e;\,ee=e,\,ea=a,\,eb=b,\,ec=c,\,ae=a,\,be=b,\,ce=c\rangle\]
Indeed, we see this set of relations is just $\mathcal{S}$, so our embedding of the free monoid as a Swift protocol ends up encoding the free monoid as the finitely-presented semigroup $\langle A\cup\{e\};\,\mathcal{S}\rangle$, but embedded in an even larger semigroup that also contains name symbols and the set of rules $\mathcal{N}$.
Now, we imagine that we uncomment the \texttt{where} clause of our protocol \texttt{P}, with the two requirements $\FormalReq{Self.A.B == C}$ and $\FormalReq{Self.B.C == Self}$. These requirements contribute two new rewrite rules to our convergent rewrite system; we will call this set $\mathcal{R}$:
\begin{gather*}
\assocsym{P}{A}.\assocsym{P}{B}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{C}\Rightarrow\protosym{P}
\end{gather*}
We can construct $\mathcal{R}$ from $R$ by replacing $\varepsilon$ with $e$ anywhere that it appears in a relation. This gives us a set of semigroup relations, and we see that $\langle A\cup\{e\}; \mathcal{S}\cup\mathcal{R} \rangle$ is a semigroup presentation of $\AR$:
\[\langle a,\,b,\,c,\,e;\,ee\sim e,\,ea\sim a,\,eb\sim b,\,ec\sim c,\,ae\sim a,\,be\sim b,\,ce\sim c,\,ab\sim c,\,bc\sim e\rangle\]
Neither the monoid presentation $M$ nor the semigroup presentation $\langle A\cup\{e\};\,\mathcal{S}\cup\mathcal{R}\rangle$ is convergent. Now consider the following set of relations $\hat{R}$:
\[\hat{R} := \{(cc,a),\,(ba,c),\,(ca,a),\,(cb,\varepsilon)\}\]
A trivial but technical calculation shows that $\langle A;\,R\cup\hat{R}\rangle$ is a convergent monoid presentation of $\AR$. Next, we transform $\hat{R}$ into a set of semigroup relations, replacing $\varepsilon$ with $e$. We call this set $\hat{\mathcal{R}}$:
\begin{gather*}
\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{C}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\assocsym{P}{B}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{C}\\
\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{A}\Rightarrow\assocsym{P}{A}\\
\assocsym{P}{C}.\assocsym{P}{B}\Rightarrow\protosym{P}
\end{gather*}
We now claim that $\langle A\cup\{e\};\,\mathcal{S}\cup\mathcal{R}\cup\hat{\mathcal{R}}\rangle$ is a convergent semigroup presentation, because we can mechanically transform any positive rewrite path over $\langle A;\,R\cup\hat{R}\rangle$ into a positive rewrite path over this semigroup presentation. The only rewrite step that does not map trivially is $x(cb\Rightarrow\varepsilon)y$, for some $x$, $y\in A^*$. The corresponding rewrite step over the semigroup presentation, $x(cb\Rightarrow e)y$, has destination term $xey$ instead of $xy$. If either one of $x$ or $y$ is non-empty, we can eliminate the occurrence of $e$ by adding a single positive rewrite step from $\mathcal{S}$. Otherwise, if $xey=e$, there is nothing to do. In any given positive rewrite path, this transformation can only add finitely many new rewrite steps involving relations from $\mathcal{S}$. Thus, confluence and termination are preserved.
It is of course not true in general that the union of two convergent rewrite systems is convergent, however in our construction it happens to work. There are no non-trivial overlaps between the elements of $\mathcal{N}$, $\mathcal{S}$ and $\mathcal{R}$. We've proven the following:
\begin{theorem}
Suppose $\AR$ is a finitely-presented monoid, $\hat{R}$ is a finite set of relations such that $\langle A;\,R\cup\hat{R}\rangle$ is a convergent monoid presentation, and both $R$ and $\hat{R}$ are oriented with respect to the shortlex order on $A^*$. We define a protocol \texttt{P} encoding $\AR$, naming the associated types in correspondence with the fixed linear order on the generating set $A$ (for example, if $a<b<c<\cdots$, we have $\assocsym{P}{A}<\assocsym{P}{B}<\assocsym{P}{C}$). Then our protocol \texttt{P} has the following \emph{convergent} presentation:
\[\langle A\cup\{e\}\cup B;\,\mathcal{N}\cup\mathcal{S}\cup\mathcal{R}\cup\hat{\mathcal{R}}\rangle\]
Here, $e:=\protosym{P}$, $B$ is a set of name symbols, $\mathcal{N}$ and $\mathcal{S}$ only depend on $A$, and $\mathcal{R}$ and $\hat{\mathcal{R}}$ are constructed from $R$ and $\hat{R}$ as above. The semigroup presented above also contains a sub-semigroup with the following convergent presentation:
\[\langle A\cup\{e\};\,\mathcal{S}\cup\mathcal{R}\cup\hat{\mathcal{R}}\rangle\]
This sub-semigroup is isomorphic to the monoid $\langle A;\,R\cup\hat{R}\rangle$ and thus $\AR$.
\end{theorem}
Hence, we see that if we encode a finitely-presented monoid $\AR$ as a protocol~\texttt{P}, the Requirement Machine will accept~\texttt{P} and solve the word problem in $\AR$ if and only if $\AR$ has a convergent presentation compatible with the shortlex order on $A^*$. That's a satisfying conclusion to ``Swift type checking is undecidable.''
Our double encoding of ``a monoid as a protocol as a rewrite system'' introduces many new symbols and relations not found in the original presentation. It is a remarkable fact of our construction then, that a convergent monoid presentation always maps to a convergent rewrite system where the added detritus can always be ``factored out.''
\end{example}
\section{Source Code Reference}\label{completion sourceref}
Key source files:
\begin{itemize}
\item \SourceFile{lib/AST/RequirementMachine/KnuthBendix.cpp}
\item \SourceFile{lib/AST/RequirementMachine/RewriteSystem.cpp}
\item \SourceFile{lib/AST/RequirementMachine/Trie.h}
\end{itemize}
\apiref{rewriting::RewriteSystem}{class}
See also Section~\ref{symbols terms rules sourceref}.
\begin{itemize}
\item \texttt{addRule()} implements Algorithm~\ref{add rule derived algo}.
\item \texttt{recordRewriteLoop()} records a \index{rewrite loop}rewrite loop if this rewrite system is used for minimization.
\item \IndexSource{critical pair}\texttt{computeCriticalPair()} implements Algorithm~\ref{critical pair algo}.
\item \IndexSource{Knuth-Bendix algorithm}\texttt{computeConfluentCompletion()} implements Algorithm~\ref{knuthbendix}.
\item \texttt{simplifyLeftHandSides()} \IndexSource{left simplification}\IndexSource{reduced rewrite system}\IndexSource{left-reduced rewrite system}implements Algorithm~\ref{left simplification}.
\item \texttt{simplifyRightHandSides()} \IndexSource{right simplification}\IndexSource{right-reduced rewrite system}implements Algorithm~\ref{right simplification}.
\end{itemize}
\apiref{rewriting::Trie}{template class}
\begin{itemize}
\item \texttt{findAll()} finds all \index{rule trie}overlapping rules using Algorithm~\ref{find overlapping rule algo}.
\end{itemize}
\end{document}
|